From the USA

Reading this position paper reminded me of George Bernard Shaw’s quip about England and America: two countries separated by the same language.’ While I easily appreciate most of the argument, some parts seem quite foreign,’ while major elements are lacking that I would expect in a review on euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide from North America. I wish the intended audience was defined. The absence of references to articles and monographs that have accompanied the heated public and professional debates on these issues in the USA suggests strict reliance on a European viewpoint. The section on `Medicalized killing’ was most anomalous. Here, the paper only refers to withholding and withdrawing `futile treatment.’ The concept of futility, while popular in the recent past, has largely been abandoned as a useful construct. More importantly, we recognize the right of patients to refuse any treatment, regardless of whether it can be construed as futile. Withholding or withdrawing a potentially life-sustaining treatment at the wish of the patient is carefully distinguished from euthanasia or assisted suicide. Likewise, sedation for intractable dist ress in the dying patient’ / a much more precise term than terminal sedation’ and less prone to misunderstanding / is generally (but not universally) accepted here as distinct from euthanasia or assisted suicide. However, no discussion of acceptable medical procedures that might hasten or cause death should omit the important and often unappreciated rule of double effect. The document does elsewhere resort to distinguishing between intended and unintended effects of treatment, a difference that, I would argue, is often hazy but is essential in applying the principal of double effect. A great deal of palliative care that might be viewed as hastening death is commonly justified by this rule, while overt terminal sedation’ is a rather rare practice. Some commentators also recognize `voluntarily stopping eating and drinking’ as an acceptable method for allowing dying patients to hasten death. Importantly, such methods that hasten death are only ethically acceptable in patients near death; broader application of euthanasia, suicide, and related approaches to self-determined’ death are rarely endorsed. The definitions of euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide also look foreign insofar as they seem to imply that only physicians can carry out euthanasia and that euthanasia and assisted suicide are solely accomplished with drugs. Other persons may carry out or assist in these acts, and other methods may be used. I do not believe the combination of barbiturates and neuromuscular blockers are `usually’ chosen for euthanasia in this country. The debate in the USA has been extremely heated, and many writers readily vilify the Dutch and advocates of legalization as somehow inhumane and ignorant of palliative care, while dismissing so much of the data that helps frame the issues in more objective terms. The document at hand seems to fall into some of these traps. For instance, it refers to legalized euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide `under certain circumstances’ without describing, for instance, the careful safeguards built into the Oregon Death with D ignity Act. I find the statement that palliative care . . . seeks to strengthen and restore autonomy, and not to destroy it’ biased and inflammatory, while the listing of only potential ills from legalized euthanasia (paragraph 4.7) suggests a one-sided view. I would have liked to see some reference to the increasing data indicating that physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia are not regularly sought because of intractable physical suffering or even depression, but rather because of concerns about control, independence, and quality of life. Likewise, the legalization of physician-assisted suicide in Oregon has led to very few uses of this optionand does not seem to have produced many of the `potential’ bad outcomes listed under paragraph 4.7. Dismissing the best data we have / from the Netherlands and now from Oregon / as having significant methodological weaknesses’ reads more like a convenient dodge than a dispassionate appraisal of the literature. The appeal to living wills and advance directives as an antidote to patients’ fears of prolonged and unbearable distress may represent wishful thinking, since the bulk of evidence indicates that these instruments are rarely prepared by patients and are then often not available to key clinicians when the documents might be useful, and finally are not respected when patient instructions conflict with what the physician believes is right. The key conclusion of the article seems to come in paragraph 4.5. `The provision of euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide should not be part of the responsibility of pallia tive care.’ The Task Force should first acknowledge that the major, challenging policy issue / Palliative Medicine 2003; 17: 104 /105

[1]  R. Burt The medical futility debate: patient choice, physician obligation, and end-of-life care. , 2002, Journal of palliative medicine.

[2]  D. J. Roy Palliative Care and Euthanasia: A Continuing Need to Think Again , 2002, Journal of palliative care.

[3]  K. Hedberg,et al.  Legalized physician-assisted suicide in Oregon, 2001. , 2002, The New England journal of medicine.

[4]  Heresa,et al.  EXPERIENCES OF OREGON NURSES AND SOCIAL WORKERS WITH HOSPICE PATIENTS WHO REQUESTED ASSISTANCE WITH SUICIDE , 2002 .

[5]  H. Nelson,et al.  Oregon physicians' attitudes about and experiences with end-of-life care since passage of the Oregon Death with Dignity Act. , 2001, JAMA.

[6]  Quill,et al.  Responding to Intractable Terminal Suffering. , 2000, Annals of internal medicine.

[7]  K. Covinsky,et al.  Communication and Decision‐Making in Seriously Ill Patients: Findings of the SUPPORT Project , 2000, Journal of the American Geriatrics Society.

[8]  H. Nelson,et al.  Physicians' experiences with the Oregon Death with Dignity Act. , 2000, The New England journal of medicine.

[9]  T. Lynch,et al.  Sedation for intractable distress of a dying patient: acute palliative care and the principle of double effect. , 2000, The oncologist.

[10]  D. Sulmasy,et al.  The rule of double effect: clearing up the double talk. , 1999, Archives of Internal Medicine.

[11]  J. J. Fins,et al.  Legalized physician-assisted suicide in Oregon. , 1999, The New England journal of medicine.

[12]  D. Meier,et al.  The Debate over Physician-Assisted Suicide: Empirical Data and Convergent Views , 1998, Annals of Internal Medicine.

[13]  B. Lo,et al.  Palliative options of last resort: a comparison of voluntarily stopping eating and drinking, terminal sedation, physician-assisted suicide, and voluntary active euthanasia. , 1997, JAMA.

[14]  R. Dresser,et al.  The rule of double effect--a critique of its role in end-of-life decision making. , 1997, The New England journal of medicine.

[15]  S. Block,et al.  Slow euthanasia. , 1996, Journal of palliative care.

[16]  D. Meier,et al.  The inaccessibility of advance directives on transfer from ambulatory to acute care settings. , 1995, JAMA.

[17]  S. Block,et al.  Patient requests to hasten death. Evaluation and management in terminal care. , 1994, Archives of internal medicine.