Symbols and Computation A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind

Over the past several decades, the philosophical community has witnessed the emergence of an important new paradigm for understanding the mind.1 The paradigm is that of machine computation, and its influence has been felt not only in philosophy, but also in all of the empirical disciplines devoted to the study of cognition. Of the several strategies for applying the resources provided by computer and cognitive science to the philosophy of mind, the one that has gained the most attention from philosophers has been the ‘Computational Theory of Mind’ (CTM). CTM was first articulated by Hilary Putnam (1960, 1961), but finds perhaps its most consistent and enduring advocate in Jerry Fodor (1975, 1980, 1981, 1987, 1990, 1994). It is this theory, and not any broader interpretations of what it would be for the mind to be a computer, that I wish to address in this paper. What I shall argue here is that the notion of ‘symbolic representation’ employed by CTM is fundamentally unsuited to providing an explanation of the intentionality of mental states (a major goal of CTM), and that this result undercuts a second major goal of CTM, sometimes refered to as the ‘vindication of intentional psychology.’ This line of argument is related to the discussions of ‘derived intentionality’ by Searle (1980, 1983, 1984) and Sayre (1986, 1987). But whereas those discussions seem to be concerned with the causal dependence of familiar sorts of symbolic representation upon meaning-bestowing acts, my claim is rather that there is not one but several notions of ‘meaning’ to be had, and that the notions that are applicable to symbols are conceptually dependent upon the notion that is applicable to mental states in the fashion that Aristotle refered to as paronymy. That is, an analysis of the notions of ‘meaning’ applicable to symbols reveals that they contain presuppositions about meaningful mental states, much as Aristotle's analysis of the sense of ‘healthy’ that is applied to foods reveals that it means ‘conducive to having a healthy body,’ and hence any attempt to explain ‘mental semantics’ in terms of the semantics of symbols is doomed to circularity and regress. I shall argue, however, that this does not have the consequence that computationalism is bankrupt as a paradigm for cognitive science, as it is possible to reconstruct CTM in a fashion that avoids these difficulties and makes it a viable research framework for psychology, albeit at the cost of losing its claims to explain intentionality and to vindicate intentional psychology. I have argued elsewhere (Horst, 1996) that local special sciences such as psychology do not require vindication in the form of demonstrating their reducibility to more fundamental theories, and hence failure to make good on these philosophical promises need not compromise the broad range of work in empirical cognitive science motivated by the computer paradigm in ways that do not depend on these problematic treatments of symbols.

[1]  Hilary Putnam,et al.  Mind, Language and Reality: Brains and behavior , 1975 .

[2]  H. Borko,et al.  Computer power and human reason: From judgement to calculation , 1976 .

[3]  Hao Wang,et al.  A survey of mathematical logic , 1963 .

[4]  S. S. Stevens,et al.  Handbook of experimental psychology , 1951 .

[5]  D. Todorović The Craik-O’Brien-Cornsweet effect: New varieties and their theoretical implications , 1987, Perception & psychophysics.

[6]  J. Fodor,et al.  A Theory of Content and Other Essays. , 1992 .

[7]  Steven Horst Symbols, Computation, and Intentionality: A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind , 1996 .

[8]  Jay L. Garfield,et al.  Belief In Psychology: A Study In The Ontology Of Mind , 1988 .

[9]  P. Strawson Intention and Convention in Speech Acts , 1964 .

[10]  G. Miller,et al.  Cognitive science. , 1981, Science.

[11]  R. Chisholm Perceiving: A Philosophical Study , 1958 .

[12]  Kenneth Mark Colby,et al.  Artificial Paranoia , 1975, Artif. Intell..

[13]  Sang Joon Kim,et al.  A Mathematical Theory of Communication , 2006 .

[14]  M. Hesse THE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY , 1969 .

[15]  John R. Searle,et al.  Minds, brains, and programs , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[16]  Keith ed Lehrer,et al.  Thomas Reid's Inquiry and Essays , 1975 .

[17]  Gerard Casey Minds and machines , 1992 .

[18]  M. Welbourne,et al.  Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism , 1990 .

[19]  C. I. Lewis,et al.  The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics , 1944 .

[20]  W S McCulloch,et al.  A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity , 1990, The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence.

[21]  Paul Ricoeur,et al.  Freud and Philosophy an Essay on Interpretation , 1970 .

[22]  D. Mitrany Methodology of the Social Sciences , 1945, Nature.

[23]  Steven Horst,et al.  Eliminativism and the ambiguity of ‘belief’ , 1995, Synthese.

[24]  J. Searle,et al.  Minds, Brains and Science , 1988 .

[25]  P. Smolensky On the proper treatment of connectionism , 1988, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[26]  Ned Block,et al.  Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology , 1987 .

[27]  Richard DeWitt Vagueness, Semantics, and the Language of Thought , 1993 .

[28]  M. Sur,et al.  Experimentally induced visual projections into auditory thalamus and cortex. , 1988, Science.

[29]  S. Grossberg,et al.  How does a brain build a cognitive code? , 1980, Psychological review.

[30]  R. Kirk Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories , 1985 .

[31]  Hubert L. Dreyfus,et al.  Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science , 1982 .

[32]  N. Swerdlow,et al.  Copernican revolution , 1975, Nature.

[33]  Simon Blackburn,et al.  Spreading the word : groundings in the philosophy of language , 1987 .

[34]  Keith Lehrer Symposiums Papers: Conception without Representation--Justification without Inference: Reid's Theory , 1989 .

[35]  R. Cummins Meaning and mental representation , 1990 .

[36]  R. Carnap Der logische Aufbau der Welt , 1998 .

[37]  N. Block Troubles with functionalism , 1993 .

[38]  Brian Loar,et al.  Conceptual role and truth-conditions: comments on Harman's paper: "Conceptual role semantics" , 1982, Notre Dame J. Formal Log..

[39]  David Papineau,et al.  Representation and Explanation , 1984, Philosophy of Science.

[40]  D Wilson,et al.  Propositional Structure and Illocutionary Force , 1979 .

[41]  Gila Sher,et al.  What is Tarski's Theory of Truth? , 1999 .

[42]  James A. Anderson,et al.  A theory for the recognition of items from short memorized lists , 1973 .

[43]  Michael Scriven,et al.  Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem , 1959 .

[44]  D. Levine Introduction to Neural and Cognitive Modeling , 2018 .

[45]  H. Putnam,et al.  Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis , 1958 .

[46]  H. Feigl,et al.  The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis , 1958 .

[47]  T. Nagel Mortal Questions: What is it like to be a bat? , 2012 .

[48]  Ausonio Marras Symbols, Computation, and Intentionality , 1999 .

[49]  R. Kirk CONVENTION: A PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY , 1970 .

[50]  H. Barlow Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information: David Marr. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1982. pp. xvi + 397 , 1983 .

[51]  G. Ryle,et al.  The concept of mind. , 2004, The International journal of psycho-analysis.

[52]  S. Stich From folk psychology to cognitive science , 1983 .

[53]  J. Fodor Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[54]  James H. Moor,et al.  Knowledge and the Flow of Information. , 1982 .

[55]  J G Daugman,et al.  Information Theory and Coding , 1998 .

[56]  G. Kanizsa Subjective contours. , 1976, Scientific American.

[57]  Gary James Jason,et al.  The Logic of Scientific Discovery , 1988 .

[58]  Ruth Garrett Millikan,et al.  Thoughts Without Laws; Cognitive Science with Content , 1986 .

[59]  Geoffrey Hunter What Computers Can't Do , 1988, Philosophy.

[60]  R. Cummins The nature of psychological explanation , 1983 .

[61]  J. Fodor The Language of Thought , 1980 .

[62]  Ken Sayre Cognitive science and the problem of semantic content , 1987, Synthese.

[63]  William P. Alston,et al.  Knowledge and the Flow of Information , 1985 .

[64]  W. E. Morris,et al.  The Philosophical Writings of Descartes , 1989 .

[65]  Terry Winograd,et al.  Understanding computers and cognition , 1986 .

[66]  John Haugeland Mind design , 1985 .

[67]  F. W. Irwin Purposive Behavior in Animals and Men , 1932, The Psychological Clinic.

[68]  J. Fodor,et al.  What psychological states are not , 1972 .

[69]  K. Sayre Intentionality and information processing: An alternative model for cognitive science , 1986, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[70]  Z. Pylyshyn Computation and cognition: issues in the foundations of cognitive science , 1980, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[71]  B. Roche,et al.  The Behavior of Organisms? , 1997 .

[72]  J. Altham Naming and necessity. , 1981 .

[73]  K. Bach,et al.  Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts , 1983 .

[74]  Daniel C. Dennett,et al.  A cure for the common code , 1978 .

[75]  E. Kingdom THE ‘MENTAL’ AND THE ‘PHYSICAL’ , 1969 .

[76]  Paul K. Feyerabend,et al.  Explanation, reduction, and empiricism , 1962 .

[77]  Kenneth M. Sayre,et al.  Consciousness : a philosophic study of minds and machines , 1972 .

[78]  John Haugeland The nature and plausibility of Cognitivism , 1978, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[79]  Daniel C. Dennett,et al.  Evolution, error, and intentionality , 1990 .

[80]  Ken Sayre Cognitive Science and the Problem of Semantic Content , 1987 .

[81]  Steven P. Horst,et al.  The Elm And The Expert , 1994 .

[82]  Hugh Lacey,et al.  The Rationality of Science , 1986 .

[83]  T. Burge Individualism and the Mental , 1979 .