Attending to the Body Action and Self-Experience in the Active Inference Framework

Endogenous attention is crucial and beneficial for learning, selecting, and supervising actions. However, deliberately attending to action execution usually comes with costs like decreased smoothness and slower performance; it may severely impair normal functioning and, in the worst case, result in pathological behavior and self-experience. These ambiguous modulatory effects of attention to action have been examined on phenomenological, computational, and implementational levels of description. The active inference framework offers a novel and potentially unifying view on these aspects, proposing that actions are enabled by attentional modulation based on expected precision of prediction errors in a brain’s hierarchical generative model. The implications of active inference fit well with empirical results, they resonate well with ideomotor action theories, and they also tentatively reflect many insights from phenomenological analysis of the “lived body”. A particular strength of active inference is its hierarchical account of motor control in terms of adaptive behavior driven by the imperative to maintain the organism’s states within unsurprising boundaries. Phenomena ranging from movement production by spinal reflex arcs to intentional, goal-directed action and the experience of oneself as an embodied agent are thus proposed to rely on the same mechanisms operating universally throughout the brain’s hierarchical generative model. However, while the explanation of movement production and sensory attenuation in terms of low-level attentional modulation is quite elegant on the active inference view, there are some questions left open by its extension to higher levels of action control—particularly about the accompanying phenomenology. I suggest that conceptual guidance from recent accounts of phenomenal selfand world-modeling may help refine the active inference framework, leading to a better understanding of the predictive nature of embodied agentive self-experience. Keywords

[1]  R. Passingham,et al.  Attention to Intention , 2004, Science.

[2]  Consciousness and Self-Regulation, Vol. 3 , 1982 .

[3]  A. Seth Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self , 2013, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[4]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Attention, Uncertainty, and Free-Energy , 2010, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[5]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Active inference and agency: optimal control without cost functions , 2012, Biological Cybernetics.

[6]  Karl J. Friston The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? , 2010, Nature Reviews Neuroscience.

[7]  J. Diedrichsen,et al.  Motor skill learning between selection and execution , 2015, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[8]  Raymond J. Dolan,et al.  Dopamine, Affordance and Active Inference , 2012, PLoS Comput. Biol..

[9]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Action and behavior: a free-energy formulation , 2010, Biological Cybernetics.

[10]  Thomas Metzinger,et al.  Motor ontology: the representational reality of goals, actions and selves , 2003 .

[11]  Karl J. Friston What Is Optimal about Motor Control? , 2011, Neuron.

[12]  Raymond J. Dolan,et al.  The anatomy of choice: active inference and agency , 2013, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[13]  Jakub Limanowski,et al.  What can body ownership illusions tell us about minimal phenomenal selfhood? , 2014, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[14]  G. Aschersleben,et al.  The Theory of Event Coding (TEC): a framework for perception and action planning. , 2001, The Behavioral and brain sciences.

[15]  Harriet BrownRick Active inference, sensory attenuation and illusions , 2013 .

[16]  A. Clark Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind , 2015 .

[17]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  A Duet for one , 2015, Consciousness and Cognition.

[18]  T. Fuchs The Psychopathology of Hyperreflexivity , 2011 .

[19]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Reinforcement Learning or Active Inference? , 2009, PloS one.

[20]  T. Egner,et al.  Bayesian modeling of flexible cognitive control , 2014, Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews.

[21]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Repetition suppression and its contextual determinants in predictive coding , 2016, Cortex.

[22]  Josef Parnas,et al.  Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. , 2003, Schizophrenia bulletin.

[23]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Predictions not commands: active inference in the motor system , 2012, Brain Structure and Function.

[24]  H. Critchley,et al.  An Interoceptive Predictive Coding Model of Conscious Presence , 2011, Front. Psychology.

[25]  Dan Zahavi,et al.  Husserl's phenomenology of the body , 1994 .

[26]  Caleb Liang,et al.  Self-as-Subject and Experiential Ownership , 2014 .

[27]  W. Prinz Perception and Action Planning , 1997 .

[28]  Anil K. Seth,et al.  The cybernetic Bayesian brain: from interoceptive inference to sensorimotor contingencies , 2014 .

[29]  Wilfried Kunde,et al.  No anticipation–no action: the role of anticipation in action and perception , 2007, Cognitive Processing.

[30]  J. Witt,et al.  Altered attention for stimuli on the hands , 2014, Cognition.

[31]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Active Inference, homeostatic regulation and adaptive behavioural control , 2015, Progress in Neurobiology.

[32]  G. Pezzulo,et al.  Navigating the Affordance Landscape: Feedback Control as a Process Model of Behavior and Cognition , 2016, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[33]  T. Metzinger Being No One: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity , 2004 .

[34]  D. Wolpert,et al.  Sensorimotor attenuation by central motor command signals in the absence of movement , 2006, Nature Neuroscience.

[35]  C. Shea,et al.  The automaticity of complex motor skill learning as a function of attentional focus , 2001, The Quarterly journal of experimental psychology. A, Human experimental psychology.

[36]  Shaun Gallagher,et al.  Lived Body and Environment , 1986 .

[37]  J. Hohwy Attention and Conscious Perception in the Hypothesis Testing Brain , 2012, Front. Psychology.

[38]  T. Metzinger,et al.  Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal selfhood , 2009, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[39]  Maurice Merleau-Ponty Phenomenology of Perception , 1964 .

[40]  Shaun Gallagher,et al.  The Oxford handbook of the self , 2011 .

[41]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  A Bayesian account of ‘hysteria’ , 2012, Brain : a journal of neurology.

[42]  D. Wolpert,et al.  Central cancellation of self-produced tickle sensation , 1998, Nature Neuroscience.

[43]  H. Bekkering,et al.  Hierarchy of Idea-Guided Action and Perception-Guided Movement , 2012, Front. Psychology.

[44]  Felix Blankenburg,et al.  Minimal self-models and the free energy principle , 2013, Front. Hum. Neurosci..

[45]  D. Spalding The Principles of Psychology , 1873, Nature.

[46]  J. Hohwy The sense of self in the phenomenology of agency and perception , 2007 .

[47]  T. Metzinger The Problem of Mental Action-Predictive Control without Sensory Sheets , 2017 .

[48]  Armin Stock,et al.  A short history of ideo-motor action , 2004, Psychological research.

[49]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Predictive coding: an account of the mirror neuron system , 2007, Cognitive Processing.

[50]  B. Hommel Action Control and the Sense of Agency , 2015 .

[51]  Karl J. Friston,et al.  Action understanding and active inference , 2011, Biological Cybernetics.