Empirical Adequacy and Ramsification

Structural realism has been proposed as an epistemological position interpolating between realism and sceptical anti-realism about scientific theories. The structural realist who accepts a scientific theory Θ thinks that Θ is empirically correct, and furthermore is a realist about the ‘structural content’ of Θ. But what exactly is ‘structural content’? One proposal is that the ‘structural content’ of a scientific theory may be associated with its Ramsey sentence ℜ(Θ). However, Demopoulos and Friedman have argued, using ideas drawn from Newman's earlier criticism of Russell's structuralism, that this move fails to achieve an interesting intermediate position between realism and anti-realism. Rather, ℜ(Θ) adds little content beyond the instrumentalistically acceptable claim that the theory Θ is empirically adequate. Here, I formulate carefully the crucial claim of Demopoulos and Friedman, and show that the Ramsey sentence ℜ(Θ) is true just in case Θ possesses a full model which is empirically correct and satisfies a certain cardinality condition on its theoretical domain. This suggests that structural realism is not a position significantly different from the anti-realism it attempts to distinguish itself from. 1. Introduction2. Technical framework3. Ramsification4. Empirical adequacy5. Ramsification ≈ empirical adequacy + cardinality constraint6. Conclusion Introduction Technical framework Ramsification Empirical adequacy Ramsification ≈ empirical adequacy + cardinality constraint Conclusion

[1]  S. Shapiro,et al.  Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic. , 1994 .

[2]  Michael Friedman,et al.  Bertrand Russell's The Analysis of Matter: Its Historical Context and Contemporary Interest , 1985, Philosophy of Science.

[3]  Volker Halbach,et al.  Conservative Theories of Classical Truth , 1999, Stud Logica.

[4]  M. H. A. Newman,et al.  I.—MR. RUSSELL'S “CAUSAL THEORY OF PERCEPTION” , 1928 .

[5]  W. V. Quine Review: Alfred Tarski, Uber den Begriff der Logischen Folgerung , 1937 .

[6]  Alfred Tarski,et al.  Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen , 1935 .

[7]  Jane English Underdetermination: Craig and Ramsey , 1973 .

[8]  J. Ladyman What is Structural Realism , 1998 .

[9]  D. Lewis How to Define Theoretical Terms , 1970 .

[10]  Vann McGee How truthlike can a predicate be? A negative result , 1985, J. Philos. Log..

[11]  Stathis Psilos Is Structural Realism the Best of Both Worlds , 2005 .

[12]  Michael Friedman,et al.  CRITICAL NOTICE: BERTRAND RUSSELL'S THE ANALYSIS OF MATTER: ITS HISTORICAL CONTEXT AND CONTEMPORARY INTEREST*t , 1985 .

[13]  Harvey M. Friedman,et al.  An axiomatic approach to self-referential truth , 1987, Ann. Pure Appl. Log..

[14]  E. Zahar Poincare's Philosophy: From Conventionalism to Phenomenology , 2001 .

[15]  Dirk van Dalen,et al.  Logic and structure , 1980 .

[16]  S. Psillos Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth , 1999 .

[17]  J Ketland,et al.  Deflationism and Tarski's paradise , 1999 .

[18]  María Manzano,et al.  Extensions of First-Order Logic , 1996 .

[19]  Jeffrey Ketland Yablo’s Paradox and ω-Inconsistency , 2005, Synthese.

[20]  J. Etchemendy The Concept of Logical Consequence , 1991 .

[21]  Grover Maxwell,et al.  Structural realism and the meaning of theoretical terms , 1970 .

[22]  Bas C. van Fraassen,et al.  The Scientific Image , 1980 .

[23]  Pierre Cruse Ramsey sentences, structural realism and trivial realization , 2005 .

[24]  A. Sokal,et al.  Defense of a Modest Scientific Realism , 2004 .