A Tale of Two Systems

In a Russian folktale, a scamp teaches a fool how to prepare a delicious soup that requires nothing but a soup stone. All one has to do is put the soup stone into boiling water. Yet, to achieve a better taste, it is desirable to add some vegetables, some meat to make the soup especially tasty, and some salt and pepper will do no harm, and so forth. A methodical examination of the development of two-system models during the past 10 years is reminiscent of the above folktale. Indeed, inspecting the different labels proposed and the various terminologies employed to characterize the presumed two systems and their corresponding alleged processes strongly suggest that it has become a stone soup where everything goes. Several authors (e.g., Gigerenzer & Reiger, 1996; Keren & Schul, 2009; Kruglanski & Gigerenzer, 2011; Osman, 2004) have critically assessed the viability and usefulness of the two-system approach. The recent expositions by Evans and Stanovich (2013, this issue, henceforth E&S) in this issue and elsewhere (e.g., Evans, 2009, 2011; Stanovich, 2009) suggest that they recognize many of the problems and seek to rectify them. Unfortunately, I suggest that their attempts are futile and, if anything, only increase confusion due to the addition of new theoretical constructs and the proposition that there may be more than two systems. My commentary has two different levels. At one level, I directly address E&S’s article, particularly commenting on what they now term a two-process theory. At a higher level, I consider E&S’s new model to be yet another version of what generically is referred to as “two-system” models and ask whether these indeed constitute theories or models as usually conceived by the scientific community. It is obviously beyond the scope of this article to provide an elaborated discussion of the nature of adequate scientific theories. Yet, it is commonly agreed that proper models should be based on well-defined constructs, motivate new questions, and yield testable predictions that will either corroborate or refute the theory under investigation. The central claim of this commentary is that none of the two-system theories, including the current version from E&S, satisfy the cardinal requirements of a scientific theory. Indeed, a previous article written in collaboration with my colleague Yaacov Schul (Keren & Schul, 2009) was meant to specify some (but certainly not all) basic requirements needed to transform two-system theories into testable ones. We realized that satisfying these requirements may be difficult, if not impossible, because these theories are so broad that they supposedly can account for almost all high-level social-cognitive phenomena. An important feature, in fact a necessary condition, for any scientific theory is a clear and unambiguous statement regarding the theory’s constraints and the corresponding boundaries. Otherwise, the theory becomes nothing but a set of arbitrary nominal definitions as the testable empirical world is not constrained. Inspection of two-system theories, including E&S’s version currently under discussion, unequivocally shows that the selective evidence they state to support their claims is, at best, consistent with the theoretical position rather than being based on direct tests derived from their theories. E&S’s article boils down to three main points: First, they agree with many of the criticisms of two-system models, yet believe that these were overstated. Second, they point out that most of the criticisms apply to a generic model, but they assert that the various models differ on different dimensions and thus should not be treated identically. Finally, they propose a new twoprocess theory that they believe is invulnerable to the common criticisms. In what follows, I briefly comment on each of these points. I close my commentary by raising two questions: First, I ask whether the current model, like its two-system predecessors, is testable in any scientific sense and probe whether the empirical evidence, brought by proponents of the theory, really supports their claims. Second, I question whether the ontological inquiry about the existence 483474 PPSXXX10.1177/1745691613483474KerenA Tale of Two Systems research-article2013

[1]  Y. Kareev Seven (indeed, plus or minus two) and the detection of correlations. , 2000, Psychological review.

[2]  N. McGlynn Thinking fast and slow. , 2014, Australian veterinary journal.

[3]  G. Keren,et al.  Two Is Not Always Better Than One , 2009, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[4]  Andrew D. Engell,et al.  Implicit working memory , 2009, Consciousness and Cognition.

[5]  V. Ramachandran,et al.  The simulating social mind: the role of the mirror neuron system and simulation in the social and communicative deficits of autism spectrum disorders. , 2007, Psychological bulletin.

[6]  R. Poldrack Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? , 2006, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[7]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  How do we tell an association from a rule , 1996 .

[8]  G. Gigerenzer,et al.  Intuitive and Deliberate Judgments Are Based on Common Principles This Article Has Been Corrected. See Last Page , 2022 .

[9]  Robyn M. Dawes,et al.  A message from psychologists to economists: mere predictability doesn’t matter like it should (without a good story appended to it) ☆ , 1999 .

[10]  Han L. J. van der Maas,et al.  Science Perspectives on Psychological an Agenda for Purely Confirmatory Research on Behalf Of: Association for Psychological Science , 2022 .

[11]  Matthew D. Lieberman,et al.  What zombies can't do: A social cognitive neuroscience approach to the irreducibility of reflective consciousness , 2012 .

[12]  T. Yarkoni Big Correlations in Little Studies: Inflated fMRI Correlations Reflect Low Statistical Power—Commentary on Vul et al. (2009) , 2009, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[13]  Jonathan Evans,et al.  Rapid responding increases belief bias: Evidence for the dual-process theory of reasoning , 2005 .

[14]  H Pashler,et al.  How persuasive is a good fit? A comment on theory testing. , 2000, Psychological review.

[15]  Jonathan Evans Intuition and Reasoning: A Dual-Process Perspective , 2010 .

[16]  P. Pollard,et al.  On the conflict between logic and belief in syllogistic reasoning , 1983, Memory & cognition.

[17]  Jonathan Evans How many dual-process theories do we need? One, two, or many? , 2009 .

[18]  Jonathan Evans,et al.  Science Perspectives on Psychological , 2022 .

[19]  L. Barsalou,et al.  Whither structured representation? , 1999, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[20]  Maya Tamir,et al.  Choosing to be afraid: preferences for fear as a function of goal pursuit. , 2009, Emotion.

[21]  Richard Henson,et al.  Forward inference using functional neuroimaging: dissociations versus associations , 2006, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[22]  How much Can we Learn from Double Dissociations? , 2003, Cortex.

[23]  L. Barsalou Situated simulation in the human conceptual system , 2003 .

[24]  H. Pashler,et al.  Puzzlingly High Correlations in fMRI Studies of Emotion, Personality, and Social Cognition 1 , 2009, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[25]  K. Stanovich Distinguishing the reflective, algorithmic, and autonomous minds: Is it time for a tri-process theory? , 2008 .

[26]  M. Osman An evaluation of dual-process theories of reasoning , 2004, Psychonomic bulletin & review.

[27]  K. Stanovich,et al.  Defining features versus incidental correlates of Type 1 and Type 2 processing , 2012 .

[28]  Y. Kareev And Yet the Small-Sample Effect Does Hold: Reply to Juslin and Olsson (2005) and Anderson, Doherty, Berg, and Friedrich (2005). , 2005 .

[29]  Maya Tamir,et al.  Preferences for sadness when eliciting help: Instrumental motives in sadness regulation , 2010 .

[30]  Priti Shah,et al.  Models of Working Memory: Models of Working Memory: An Introduction , 1999 .

[31]  Ran R. Hassin,et al.  Nonconscious Goal Pursuit in Novel Environments , 2008, Psychological science.

[32]  D. Navon Resources—a theoretical soup stone? , 1984 .

[33]  S. Newstead Are there two different types of thinking? , 2000, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[34]  K. Fiedler Voodoo Correlations Are Everywhere—Not Only in Neuroscience , 2011, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[35]  A. Miyake,et al.  Models of Working Memory: Mechanisms of Active Maintenance and Executive Control , 1999 .