Replication, Communication, and the Population Dynamics of Scientific Discovery

Many published research results are false (Ioannidis, 2005), and controversy continues over the roles of replication and publication policy in improving the reliability of research. Addressing these problems is frustrated by the lack of a formal framework that jointly represents hypothesis formation, replication, publication bias, and variation in research quality. We develop a mathematical model of scientific discovery that combines all of these elements. This model provides both a dynamic model of research as well as a formal framework for reasoning about the normative structure of science. We show that replication may serve as a ratchet that gradually separates true hypotheses from false, but the same factors that make initial findings unreliable also make replications unreliable. The most important factors in improving the reliability of research are the rate of false positives and the base rate of true hypotheses, and we offer suggestions for addressing each. Our results also bring clarity to verbal debates about the communication of research. Surprisingly, publication bias is not always an obstacle, but instead may have positive impacts—suppression of negative novel findings is often beneficial. We also find that communication of negative replications may aid true discovery even when attempts to replicate have diminished power. The model speaks constructively to ongoing debates about the design and conduct of science, focusing analysis and discussion on precise, internally consistent models, as well as highlighting the importance of population dynamics.

[1]  A. Hoffman,et al.  Neutral models in biology , 1987 .

[2]  P. Smaldino,et al.  Theory development with agent-based models , 2015 .

[3]  Andrew Gelman,et al.  Ethics and Statistics: The AAA Tranche of Subprime Science , 2014 .

[4]  P. Kitcher Reviving the Sociology of Science , 2000, Philosophy of Science.

[5]  David L. Hull,et al.  Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science, David L. Hull. 1988. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL. 608 pages. ISBN: 0-226-35060-4. $39.95 , 1989 .

[6]  Simone Schnall,et al.  Clean Data: Statistical Artefacts Wash Out Replication Efforts , 2014 .

[7]  Matthew C. Makel,et al.  Replications in Psychology Research , 2012, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[8]  Gerd Gigerenzer,et al.  Do Studies of Statistical Power Have an Effect on the Power of Studies? , 2004 .

[9]  J. Wicherts,et al.  Outlier removal, sum scores, and the inflation of the Type I error rate in independent samples t tests: the power of alternatives and recommendations. , 2014, Psychological methods.

[10]  Karl R. Popper,et al.  The Myth of the Framework , 1994 .

[11]  Patrick F. Sullivan,et al.  Spurious Genetic Associations , 2007, Biological Psychiatry.

[12]  J. Henrich,et al.  Markets, Religion, Community Size, and the Evolution of Fairness and Punishment , 2010, Science.

[13]  A. Detsky,et al.  Meta-analysis in medical research: strong encouragement for higher quality in individual research efforts. , 1989, Journal of clinical epidemiology.

[14]  G. Gigerenzer,et al.  Do studies of statistical power have an effect on the power of studies , 1989 .

[15]  Karl Raimund Sir Popper,et al.  The Myth of the Framework : In Defence of Science and Rationality , 1997 .

[16]  K. Popper,et al.  Conjectures and refutations;: The growth of scientific knowledge , 1972 .

[17]  J. Ioannidis Why Most Published Research Findings Are False , 2005, PLoS medicine.

[18]  Marco Fontani,et al.  The Lost Elements: The Periodic Table's Shadow Side , 2014 .

[19]  B. Latour,et al.  Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. , 1990 .

[20]  Douglas W. Yu,et al.  Human preferences for sexually dimorphic faces may be evolutionarily novel , 2014, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

[21]  Neil Malhotra,et al.  Publication bias in the social sciences: Unlocking the file drawer , 2014, Science.

[22]  Helge Kragh,et al.  The Lost Elements: The Periodic Table's Shadow Side , 2016, Ambix.

[23]  F. Prinz,et al.  Believe it or not: how much can we rely on published data on potential drug targets? , 2011, Nature Reviews Drug Discovery.

[24]  K. Popper,et al.  Conjectures and refutations;: The growth of scientific knowledge , 1972 .

[25]  D. Campbell Toward an Epistemologically-Relevant Sociology of Science* , 1985 .

[26]  M. Brent Donnellan,et al.  Commentary and Rejoinder on Johnson, Cheung, and Donnellan (2014a) , 2014 .

[27]  C. Begley,et al.  Drug development: Raise standards for preclinical cancer research , 2012, Nature.

[28]  Leif D. Nelson,et al.  False-Positive Psychology , 2011, Psychological science.

[29]  John Bohannon,et al.  Psychology. Replication effort provokes praise--and 'bullying' charges. , 2014, Science.

[30]  R. T. Cox Probability, frequency and reasonable expectation , 1990 .

[31]  Brian A. Nosek,et al.  Power failure: why small sample size undermines the reliability of neuroscience , 2013, Nature Reviews Neuroscience.

[32]  R. Levins The strategy of model building in population biology , 1966 .

[33]  Daniel Kahneman,et al.  A new etiquette for replication. , 2014 .

[34]  Neil Malhotra,et al.  Publication Bias in the Social Sciences , 2014 .

[35]  Mina Bissell,et al.  Reproducibility: The risks of the replication drive , 2013, Nature.

[36]  Brian A. Nosek,et al.  Power failure: why small sample size undermines the reliability of neuroscience , 2013, Nature Reviews Neuroscience.

[37]  S. Schmidt Shall we Really do it Again? The Powerful Concept of Replication is Neglected in the Social Sciences , 2009 .

[38]  N. Stanietsky,et al.  The interaction of TIGIT with PVR and PVRL2 inhibits human NK cell cytotoxicity , 2009, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

[39]  R. Rosenthal The file drawer problem and tolerance for null results , 1979 .