What we know and what to do

This paper discusses an important puzzle about the semantics of indicative conditionals and deontic necessity modals (should, ought, etc.): the Miner Puzzle (Parfit, ms; Kolodny and MacFarlane, J Philos 107:115–143, 2010). Rejecting modus ponens for the indicative conditional, as others have proposed, seems to solve a version of the puzzle, but is actually orthogonal to the puzzle itself. In fact, I prove that the puzzle arises for a variety of sophisticated analyses of the truth-conditions of indicative conditionals. A comprehensive solution requires rethinking the relationship between relevant information (what we know) and practical rankings of possibilities and actions (what to do). I argue that (i) relevant information determines whether considerations of value may be treated as reasons for actions that realize them and against actions that don’t, (ii) incorporating this normative fact requires a revision of the standard ordering semantics for weak (but not for strong) deontic necessity modals, and (iii) an off-the-shelf semantics for weak deontic necessity modals, due to von Fintel and Iatridou, which distinguishes “basic” and “higher-order” ordering sources, and interprets weak deontic necessity modals relative to both, is well-suited to this task. The prominence of normative considerations in our proposal suggests a more general methodological lesson: formal semantic analysis of natural language modals expressing normative concepts demands that close attention be paid to the nature of the underlying normative phenomena.

[1]  M. Burnyeat Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy: Aristotle on learning to be good , 2012 .

[2]  Robert Stalnaker A Theory of Conditionals , 2019, Knowledge and Conditionals.

[3]  Paul Weirich Conditional Utility and Its Place in Decision Theory , 1980 .

[4]  Aaron Sloman,et al.  IV.—‘OUGHT’ AND ‘BETTER’ , 1970 .

[5]  Eric Swanson,et al.  On the Treatment of Incomparability in Ordering Semantics and Premise Semantics , 2011, J. Philos. Log..

[6]  Hector-Neri Castañeda,et al.  ‘Ought’ and ‘Better’ , 1973 .

[7]  Fabrizio Cariani,et al.  Deliberative modality under epistemic uncertainty , 2013 .

[8]  D. Wiggins II—Deliberation and Practical Reason , 1976 .

[9]  A. Sloman ‘ OUGHT ’ AND ‘ BETTER ’ , 2011 .

[10]  H. D. Swart,et al.  Adverbs of quantification , 1991 .

[11]  K. Fintel,et al.  What to Do If You Want to Go to Harlem: Anankastic Conditionals and Related Matters∗ , 2005 .

[12]  Dilip Ninan Mit Two Puzzles About Deontic Necessity , 2005 .

[13]  A. Kratzer The Notional Category of Modality , 2008 .

[14]  R. Rooij Conjunctive interpretation of disjunction , 2010 .

[15]  Eric H. Swanson Modality in Language , 2008 .

[16]  P. Portner Imperatives and modals , 2007 .

[17]  T. Stephenson Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste , 2007 .

[18]  N. Belnap Backwards and Forwards in the Modal Logic of Agency , 1991 .

[19]  John MacFarlane,et al.  Ifs and Oughts , 2010 .

[20]  S. Yalcin Epistemic Modals , 2007 .

[21]  Kai von Fintel,et al.  How to Say Ought in Foreign: The Composition of Weak Necessity Modals , 2008 .

[22]  Edward L. Keenan,et al.  Formal Semantics of Natural Language , 1975 .

[23]  Nuel D. Belnap,et al.  Seeing To it That: A Canonical Form for Agentives , 2008 .

[24]  J. MacFarlane Epistemic Modals Are Assessment‐Sensitive , 2011 .

[25]  J. Stanley,et al.  Knowledge and Action , 2008 .

[26]  James Dreier RELATIVISM (AND EXPRESSIVISM) AND THE PROBLEM OF DISAGREEMENT , 2009 .

[27]  Jaakko Hintikka,et al.  Time And Modality , 1958 .

[28]  Dov M. Gabbay,et al.  Handbook of Philosophical Logic , 2002 .

[29]  Amartya Sen,et al.  Quasi-Transitivity, Rational Choice and Collective Decisions , 1969 .