Zoon Politicon: The evolutionary roots of human sociopolitical systems

Our primate ancestors evolved a complex sociopolitical order based on a social dominance hierarchy in multi-male/multi-female groups. The emergence of bipedalism and cooperative breeding in the hominin line, together with environmental developments which made a diet of meat from large animals fi tness enhancing, as well as cultural innovation in the form of fi re and cooking, created a niche for hominins in which there was a high return to coordinated, cooperative scavenging or hunting of large mammals. This, in turn, led to the use of stones and spears as lethal weapons. The availability of lethal weapons in early hominin society undermined the standard social dominance hierarchy of multi-male/multi-female primates. The successful sociopolitical structure that replaced the ancestral social dominance hierarchy was a political system in which success depended on the ability of leaders to persuade and motivate. This system persisted until cultural changes in the Holocene fostered the accumulation of material wealth, through which it became possible once again to sustain a social dominance hierarchy, because elites could now surround themselves with male relatives and paid protectors. This scenario suggests that humans are predisposed to seek dominance when this is not excessively costly, but also to form coalitions to depose pretenders to power. Much of human political history is the working out of these oppositional forces. Self-Interest and Cultural Hegemony Models of Political Power For half a century following the end of World War II, the behavioral sciences were dominated by two highly contrasting models of human political behavior. In biology, political science, and economics, a self-interest model held sway, wherein individuals are rational self-regarding maximizers. In sociology, social psychology, and anthropology, by contrast, a cultural hegemony model 26 H. Gintis and C. van Schaik was generally accepted. In this model, individuals are the passive internalizers of the culture in which they operate. The dominant culture, in turn, supplies the norms and values associated with role-performance, so individual behavior meets the requirements of the various roles individuals are called upon to play in daily life (Durkheim 1933/1902; Parsons 1967; Mead 1963). Contemporary research has been kind to neither model. There has always been an undercurrent of objection to the cultural hegemony model, which Dennis Wrong (1961) aptly called the “oversocialized conception of man.” Behavioral ecology alternatives were offered by Konrad Lorenz (1963), Robert Ardrey (1966/1997) and Desmond Morris (1999/1967), a line of thought that culminated in Edward O. Wilson’s Sociobiology: The New Synthesis (1975), the resurrection of human nature in Donald Brown’s Human Universals (1991), and Leda Cosmides and John Tooby’s withering attack in The Adapted Mind on the so-called “standard social science model” of cultural hegemony (Barkow et al. 1992). Meanwhile, the analytical foundations of an alternative model, that of gene–culture coevolution (see below), were laid by C. J. Lumsden and Edward O. Wilson (1981), Luca Cavalli-Sforza and Marcus Feldman (1973, 1981), and Robert Boyd and Peter Richerson (1985). In opposition to cultural hegemony theory, daily life provides countless examples of the fragility of dominant cultures. African-Americans in the era of the civil rights movement, for instance, rejected a powerful ideology that justifyied segregation, American women in the 1960s rejected a deep-rooted patriarchal culture, and gay Americans rejected traditional Judeo-Christian treatments of homosexuality. In succeeding years, each of these minority countercultures was largely accepted by the American public. In the Soviet Union, Communist leaders attempted to forge a dominant culture of socialist morality by subjecting two generations of citizens to rigid and intensive indoctrination. This failed to take hold and, following the fall of the USSR, was rejected whole cloth, without the need for extensive counter-indoctrination. Similar examples could be given from the political experience of many other countries, possibly all. Undermining the self-interest model began with the ultimatum game experiments of Güth et al. (1982), Roth et al. (1991), and many others. These experiments showed that human subjects may reject positive offers in an anonymous one-shot money-sharing situation if they fi nd the split to be unfair. The experiments of Fehr and Gächter (2000, 2002) showed that cooperation could be sustained in a fi nitely repeated public goods game if the punishing of free riders is permitted, despite the fact that the self-interest model predicts no cooperation. These and related fi ndings have led in recent years to a revision of the received wisdom in biology and economics toward the appreciation of the central importance of other-regarding preferences and character virtues in biological and economic theory (Gintis et al. 2005; Henrich et al. 2005; Okasha and Binmore 2012) Zoon Politicon: Roots of Human Sociopolitical Systems 27 The untenability of the self-interest model of human action is also clear from everyday experience. Political activity in modern societies provides unambiguous evidence. In large democratic elections, the rational self-regarding agent will not vote because the costs of voting are positive and signifi cant, but the probability that one vote will alter the outcome of the election is vanishingly small. Thus the personal gain from voting is vanishingly small. For similar reasons, if one chooses to vote, there is no plausible reason to vote on the basis of the impact of the outcome of the election on one’s self-regarding gains. It follows also that the voter, if rational, self-regarding, and incapable of personally infl uencing the opinions of more than a few others, will not bother to form opinions on political issues, because these opinions cannot affect the outcome of elections. Yet people do vote, and many do expend time and energy in forming political opinions. This behavior does not conform to the selfinterest model. It is a short step from the irrefutable logic of self-regarding political behavior that rational self-regarding individuals will not participate in the sort of collective actions that are responsible for growth in the world of representative and democratic governance, the respect for civil liberties, the rights of minorities and women in public life, and the like. In the self-interest model, only small groups of individuals aspiring to social dominance will act politically. Yet modern egalitarian political institutions are the result of such collective actions (Bowles and Gintis 1986; Giugni et al. 1998). This behavior cannot be explained by the self-interest model. Apart from professional politicians and socially infl uential individuals, electoral politics is a vast morality play in which models of the rational selfregarding actor are not only a poor fi t, but are conceptually bizarre. It took Mancur Olson’s The Logic of Collective Action (1965) to make this clear to many behavioral scientists, because virtually all students of social life had assumed, without refl ection, the faulty logic that rational self-regarding individuals will vote, and will “vote their interests” (Downs 1957). Defenders of the self-interest model may respond that voters believe their votes make a difference, however untenable this belief might be under logical scrutiny. Indeed, when asked why they vote, voters’ common response is that they are trying to help get one or another party elected to offi ce. When apprised of the illogical character of that response, the common reply is that there are in fact close elections, where the balance is tipped in one direction or another by only a few hundred votes. When confronted with the fact that one vote will not affect even such close elections, the common repost is that “Well, if everyone thought like that, we couldn’t run a democracy.” Politically active and informed citizens appear to operate on the principle that voting is both a duty and prerogative of citizenship, an altruistic act that is justifi ed by the categorical imperative: act in conformance with the morally correct behavior for individuals in one’s position, without regard to personal costs and benefi ts. Such mental reasoning, which has been called “shared 28 H. Gintis and C. van Schaik intentionality,” is implicated in many uniquely human cognitive characteristics, including cumulative culture and language (Sugden 2003; Bacharach 2006). Shared intentionality rests on a fundamentally prosocial disposition (Gilbert 1987; Bratman 1993; Tomasello and Carpenter 2007; Hrdy 2009). Human beings acting in the public sphere are, then, neither docile internalizers of dominant culture nor sociopathic personal gain maximizers. Rather, they are generally what Aristotle called zoon politikon—political beings (Aristotle 350 BC/2002). In this chapter we lay out a rather general framework for understanding this deep property of the human psyche, drawing in various ways on all the behavioral sciences. This framework will be used to elucidate the role of basic human political predispositions in creating and transforming sociopolitical structures. The Political and Economic Structure of Primate Societies Humans are one of more than two hundred extant species belonging to the Primate order. All primates have sociopolitical systems for regulating social life within their communities. Understanding human sociopolitical organization involves specifying how and why humans are similar to and different from other primate species. Similarities likely indicate that the trait was already present before humans evolved. For instance, many primate species, including humans, seek to dominate others and are adept at forming coalitions. It is thus likely that their common ancestor also possessed these traits. Dominance seeking and coalition

[1]  R. Ardrey The Territorial Imperative: A Personal Inquiry Into the Animal Origins of Property and Nations , 2014 .

[2]  J. Lehmann,et al.  Fitness-related benefits of dominance in primates. , 2012, American journal of physical anthropology.

[3]  Carel P. van Schaik,et al.  Impartial Third-Party Interventions in Captive Chimpanzees: A Reflection of Community Concern , 2012, PloS one.

[4]  P. Villa,et al.  On the earliest evidence for habitual use of fire in Europe , 2011, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

[5]  B. Hewlett,et al.  Co-Residence Patterns in Hunter-Gatherer Societies Show Unique Human Social Structure , 2011, Science.

[6]  R. Wrangham,et al.  Human adaptation to the control of fire , 2010 .

[7]  C. V. van Schaik,et al.  Tolerant food sharing and reciprocity is precluded by despotism among bonobos but not chimpanzees. , 2010, American journal of physical anthropology.

[8]  R. Boyd,et al.  Coordinated Punishment of Defectors Sustains Cooperation and Can Proliferate When Rare , 2010, Science.

[9]  Jessica C. Flack,et al.  The emergence of simple and complex power structures through social niche construction. , 2010 .

[10]  A. Plourde Human Power and Prestige Systems , 2010 .

[11]  John C. Avise,et al.  The Cognitive Niche: Coevolution of Intelligence, Sociality, and Language , 2010 .

[12]  Carel P. van Schaik,et al.  Mind the Gap: Cooperative Breeding and the Evolution of Our Unique Features , 2010 .

[13]  Paul L. Hooper,et al.  Intergenerational Wealth Transmission and the Dynamics of Inequality in Small-Scale Societies , 2009, Science.

[14]  Judith M Burkart,et al.  Cooperative breeding and human cognitive evolution , 2009 .

[15]  A. Gopher,et al.  Cooperative hunting and meat sharing 400–200 kya at Qesem Cave, Israel , 2009, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

[16]  Carel P. van Schaik,et al.  Cognitive consequences of cooperative breeding in primates? , 2009, Animal Cognition.

[17]  N. Alperson-Afil Continual fire-making by Hominins at Gesher Benot Ya‘aqov, Israel , 2008 .

[18]  M. Bastian,et al.  Life history costs and benefits of encephalization: a comparative test using data from long-term studies of primates in the wild. , 2008, Journal of human evolution.

[19]  I. Martínez,et al.  Human hyoid bones from the middle Pleistocene site of the Sima de los Huesos (Sierra de Atapuerca, Spain). , 2008, Journal of human evolution.

[20]  J. Montgomery Beyond Individual Choice: Teams and Frames in Game Theory. By Michael Bacharach. Edited by, Natalie Gold and Robert Sugden. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2006. Pp. 240. $35.00. , 2007 .

[21]  H. Vries,et al.  Sex Differences in the Steepness of Dominance Hierarchies in Captive Bonobo Groups , 2007, International Journal of Primatology.

[22]  Brian Hare,et al.  Tolerance Allows Bonobos to Outperform Chimpanzees on a Cooperative Task , 2007, Current Biology.

[23]  J. Pruetz,et al.  Savanna Chimpanzees, Pan troglodytes verus, Hunt with Tools , 2007, Current Biology.

[24]  K. Milton Habitat, diet, and activity patterns of free-ranging woolly spider monkeys (Brachyteles arachnoides E. Geoffroy 1806) , 1984, International Journal of Primatology.

[25]  D. Maestripieri Macachiavellian Intelligence: How Rhesus Macaques and Humans Have Conquered the World , 2007 .

[26]  P. Wiessner From Spears to M-16s: Testing the Imbalance of Power Hypothesis among the Enga , 2006, Journal of Anthropological Research.

[27]  C. Boesch,et al.  Male competition and paternity in wild chimpanzees of the Taï forest. , 2006, American journal of physical anthropology.

[28]  M. Domínguez‐Rodrigo,et al.  New estimates of tooth mark and percussion mark frequencies at the FLK Zinj site: the carnivore-hominid-carnivore hypothesis falsified. , 2006, Journal of human evolution.

[29]  T. Furuichi Sexual swelling, receptivity, and grouping of wild pygmy chimpanzee females at Wamba, Zaïre , 1987, Primates.

[30]  Sagar A. Pandit,et al.  Chapter 9: Toward a general model for male-male coalitions in primate groups , 2006 .

[31]  Colin Camerer,et al.  “Economic man” in cross-cultural perspective: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies , 2005, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[32]  M. Tomasello,et al.  Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition , 2005, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[33]  W. McGrew,et al.  The Cultured Chimpanzee: Reflections on Cultural Primatology , 2004 .

[34]  E. Carbonell,et al.  Auditory capacities in Middle Pleistocene humans from the Sierra de Atapuerca in Spain. , 2004, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.

[35]  C. Schaik,et al.  Sexual Selection in Primates: Mating conflict in primates: infanticide, sexual harassment and female sexuality , 2004 .

[36]  Margaret Gilbert Modelling collective belief , 1987, Synthese.

[37]  Sagar A. Pandit,et al.  A model for leveling coalitions among primate males: toward a theory of egalitarianism , 2003, Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology.

[38]  R. Sugden The Logic of Team Reasoning , 2003 .

[39]  K. Hawkes,et al.  Male strategies and Plio-Pleistocene archaeology. , 2002, Journal of human evolution.

[40]  C. Boesch,et al.  Behavioural Diversity in Chimpanzees and Bonobos , 2002 .

[41]  J. O'connell,et al.  Cut and Tooth Mark Distributions on Large Animal Bones: Ethnoarchaeological Data from the Hadza and Their Implications For Current Ideas About Early Human Carnivory , 2002 .

[42]  M. Stiner Carnivory, Coevolution, and the Geographic Spread of the Genus Homo , 2002 .

[43]  D.,et al.  THE EVOLUTION OF SOCIAL BEHAVIOR , 2002 .

[44]  Robert L. Bettinger,et al.  Was Agriculture Impossible during the Pleistocene but Mandatory during the Holocene? A Climate Change Hypothesis , 2001, American Antiquity.

[45]  C. Ember Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution of Egalitarian Behavior , 2001 .

[46]  Lucilla Spini Bonobo – The Forgotten Ape. By Frans de Waal & Frans Lanting. Pp. 210 (University of California Press, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London, 1997.) £24·95, ISBN 0–520–21651–2, paperback. , 2001 .

[47]  Lawrence S. Sugiyama,et al.  Effects of Illness and Injury on Foraging Among the Yora and Shiwiar: Pathology Risk as Adaptive Problem , 2017 .

[48]  H. Gintis Strong reciprocity and human sociality. , 2000, Journal of theoretical biology.

[49]  C. Schaik,et al.  Infanticide by males and its implications: The other side of the coin: infanticide and the evolution of affiliative male–infant interactions in Old World primates , 2000 .

[50]  G. Miller The Mating Mind: How Sexual Choice Shaped the Evolution of Human Nature , 2000 .

[51]  Kim Hill,et al.  A theory of human life history evolution: Diet, intelligence, and longevity , 2000 .

[52]  P. Bingham,et al.  Human Uniqueness: A General Theory , 1999, The Quarterly Review of Biology.

[53]  D. Wrong,et al.  The oversocialized conception of man , 1999 .

[54]  S. Hrdy,et al.  Mother Nature: Maternal Instincts and How They Shape the Human Species , 1999 .

[55]  Carel P. van Schaik,et al.  The evolution of female social relationships in nonhuman primates , 1997, Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology.

[56]  R. Wrangham,et al.  Demonic Males: Apes and the Origins of Human Violence , 1997 .

[57]  H. Thieme Lower Palaeolithic hunting spears from Germany , 1997, Nature.

[58]  Kazuhiko Hosaka,et al.  Great Ape Societies: Coalition strategies among adult male chimpanzees of the Mahale Mountains, Tanzania , 1996 .

[59]  R. Potts Humanity's Descent: The Consequences of Ecological Instability , 1996 .

[60]  R. L. Kelly The Foraging Spectrum: Diversity in Hunter-Gatherer Lifeways , 1997 .

[61]  R. Blumenschine,et al.  Competition for carcasses and early hominid behavioral ecology: A case study and conceptual framework , 1994 .

[62]  J. Steele Climate and Human Progress: Being Human: Putting People in an EvolutionaryPerspective by Mary & John Gribbin, 1993,London: J.M. Dent. 292pp. , 1994 .

[63]  Michael E. Bratman,et al.  Shared Intention , 1993, Ethics.

[64]  Robert Ascher,et al.  The Human Revolution , 1992, Current Anthropology.

[65]  S. Zamir,et al.  Bargaining and Market Behavior in Jerusalem, Ljubljana, Pittsburgh, and Tokyo: An Experimental Study , 1991 .

[66]  Keith F. Otterbein,et al.  Violence and Sociality in Human Evolution [and Comments and Replies] , 1991, Current Anthropology.

[67]  R. Byrne,et al.  Machiavellian intelligence : social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes, and humans , 1990 .

[68]  Barbara Isaac,et al.  Throwing and human evolution , 1987 .

[69]  F. Fifer The adoption of bipedalism by the hominids: A new hypothesis , 1987 .

[70]  W. Wagner,et al.  Democracy and Capitalism: Property, Community, and the Contradictions of Modern Social Thought , 1987 .

[71]  K. Strier Activity budgets of woolly spider monkeys, or muriquis (Brachyteles arachnoides) , 1987, American journal of primatology.

[72]  D. E. Stuart,et al.  Food Sharing Among Ache Foragers: Tests of Explanatory Hypotheses [and Comments and Reply] , 1985, Current Anthropology.

[73]  W H Calvin,et al.  A stone's throw and its launch window: timing precision and its implications for language and hominid brains. , 1983, Journal of theoretical biology.

[74]  C. Schaik Why Are Diurnal Primates Living in Groups , 1983 .

[75]  Edward O. Wilson,et al.  Genes, Mind and Culture: The Coevolutionary Process. , 1982 .

[76]  R. Wrangham An Ecological Model of Female-Bonded Primate Groups , 1980 .

[77]  Morris Dembo,et al.  Origins of the State and Civilization , 1976 .

[78]  N. Humphrey The Social Function of Intellect , 1976 .

[79]  Group selection, altruism, reinforcement, and throwing in human evolution. , 1975, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.

[80]  E. Wilson Sociobiology. The New Synthesis. Cambridge, MA (The Belknap Press) 1975. , 1975 .

[81]  T. H. Clutton-Brock,et al.  Primate social organisation and ecology , 1974, Nature.

[82]  M W Feldman,et al.  Models for cultural inheritance. I. Group mean and within group variation. , 1973, Theoretical population biology.

[83]  A. Jolly The Evolution of Primate Behavior , 1972 .

[84]  Desmond Morris,et al.  The naked ape : a zoologist's study of the human animal , 1968 .

[85]  Morton H. Fried,et al.  The Evolution of Political Society: An Essay in Political Anthropology , 1967 .

[86]  M. Olson,et al.  The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups , 1969 .

[87]  K. Lorenz On aggression, New York (Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.) 1966. , 1966 .

[88]  J. Goodall,et al.  Tool-Using and Aimed Throwing in a Community of Free-Living Chimpanzees , 1964, Nature.

[89]  A. Downs An Economic Theory of Democracy , 1957 .

[90]  R. Punnett,et al.  The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection , 1930, Nature.

[91]  R. Dart Australopithecus africanus: The Man-Ape of South Africa , 1925, Nature.