Gain-Loss Separability and Coalescing in Risky Decision Making

This experiment tested two behavioral properties of risky decision making---gain-loss separability (GLS) and coalescing. Cumulative prospect theory (CPT) implies both properties, but the transfer of attention exchange (TAX) model violates both. Original prospect theory satisfies GLS but may or may not satisfy coalescing, depending on whether editing rules are assumed. A configural form of CPT proposed by Wu and Markle [Wu, G., A. B. Markle. 2004. An empirical test of gain-loss separability in prospect theory. Working Paper 06-25-04, Graduate School of Business, University of Chicago] violates GLS, but satisfies coalescing. New tests were designed and conducted to test these theories against specific predictions of a TAX model. This model used parameters estimated from previous data, together with simple new assumptions to extend TAX to gambles with negative and mixed consequences. Contrary to all three forms of prospect theory, systematic violations of both coalescing and GLS were observed. Violations of GLS were confirmed by analyses of individual data patterns by means of an error model in which each choice can have a different rate of error. Without estimating any parameters from the new data, the TAX model predicted the majority choices in the new data fairly well, correctly predicting when modal choices would violate GLS, when they would satisfy it, and when indifference would be observed.

[1]  Robert Sugden,et al.  Testing for juxtaposition and event-splitting effects , 1993 .

[2]  Peter P. Wakker,et al.  The Data of Levy and Levy (2002) "Prospect Theory: Much Ado About Nothing?" Actually Support Prospect Theory , 2003, Manag. Sci..

[3]  Steven J. Humphrey Regret aversion or event-splitting effects? more evidence under risk and uncertainty , 1995 .

[4]  M. Birnbaum,et al.  Source Credibility in Social Judgment : Bias , Expertise , and the Judge ' s Point of View , 1979 .

[5]  R. Luce Utility of Gains and Losses: Measurement-Theoretical and Experimental Approaches , 2000 .

[6]  J. Quiggin,et al.  Generalized Expected Utility Theory. The Rank-Dependent Model , 1996 .

[7]  A. Tversky,et al.  Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk — Source link , 2007 .

[8]  Barbara A. Mellers,et al.  Decision science and technology. Reflections on the contributions of Ward Edwards , 1999 .

[9]  P. Fishburn,et al.  Rank- and sign-dependent linear utility models for finite first-order gambles , 1991 .

[10]  Barry Sopher,et al.  Intransitive cycles: Rational choice or random error? An answer based on estimation of error rates with experimental data , 1993 .

[11]  H. Fennema,et al.  Measuring the Utility of Losses by Means of the Tradeoff Method , 1998 .

[12]  M. Birnbaum,et al.  Testing Descriptive Utility Theories: Violations of Stochastic Dominance and Cumulative Independence , 1998 .

[13]  M. Birnbaum Causes of Allais common consequence paradoxes: An experimental dissection ☆ , 2004 .

[14]  John D. Hey,et al.  Which Error Story is Best? , 2000, Experiments in Economics.

[15]  John H. Kagel,et al.  Testing between alternative models of choice under uncertainty: Some initial results , 1990 .

[16]  M. Birnbaum Tests of rank-dependent utility and cumulative prospect theory in gambles represented by natural frequencies: Effects of format, event framing, and branch splitting , 2004 .

[17]  A. Tversky,et al.  Prospect theory: analysis of decision under risk , 1979 .

[18]  C. Starmer Developments in Non-expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk , 2000 .

[19]  Alex B. Markle,et al.  An Empirical Test of Gain-Loss Separability in Prospect Theory , 2008, Manag. Sci..

[20]  Michael H. Birnbaum,et al.  Three New Tests of Independence That Differentiate Models of Risky Decision Making , 2005, Manag. Sci..

[21]  H. Zank,et al.  Loss Averse Behavior , 2005 .

[22]  Michael H. Birnbaum,et al.  The Paradoxes of Allais, Stochastic Dominance, and Decision Weights , 1999 .

[23]  P. Fishburn,et al.  A note on deriving rank-dependent utility using additive joint receipts , 1995 .

[24]  David W Harless,et al.  The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories , 1994 .

[25]  W. Edwards Subjective probabilities inferred from decisions. , 1962, Psychological review.

[26]  Michael H. Birnbaum Violations of monotonicity in judgment and decision making. , 1997 .

[27]  Peter P. Wakker,et al.  An index of loss aversion , 2005, J. Econ. Theory.

[28]  M. Birnbaum Testing Critical Properties of Decision Making on the Internet , 1999 .

[29]  R. Luce,et al.  Ranked Additive Utility Representations of Gambles: Old and New Axiomatizations , 2004 .

[30]  R. Duncan Luce,et al.  Ranked-Weighted Utilities and Qualitative Convolution , 2001 .

[31]  Moshe Levy,et al.  Prospect Theory: Much Ado About Nothing? , 2002, Manag. Sci..

[32]  M. Birnbaum The nonadditivity of personality impressions. , 1974, Journal of experimental psychology.

[33]  R. Luce,et al.  Independence Properties Vis-À-Vis Several Utility Representations , 2004 .

[34]  A.A.J. Marley,et al.  On Elements of Chance , 2000 .

[35]  A. Tversky,et al.  Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty , 1992 .

[36]  J. Quiggin A theory of anticipated utility , 1982 .

[37]  M. D. Wilkinson,et al.  Management science , 1989, British Dental Journal.

[38]  S. Traub,et al.  An Experimental Test of Loss Aversion , 2002 .

[39]  M. Birnbaum,et al.  Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes Tests of Theories of Decision Making: Violations of Branch Independence and Distribution Independence Generic Rank-dependent Utility Generic Analysis of Violations of Branch Independence and Distribution Independence Birnbaum and Mcintosh Model: N , 2022 .