When scientific models represent

Scientific models represent aspects of the empirical world. I explore to what extent this representational relationship, given the specific properties of models, can be analysed in terms of propositions to which truth or falsity can be attributed. For example, models frequently entail false propositions despite the fact that they are intended to say something "truthful" about phenomena. I argue that the representational relationship is constituted by model users "agreeing" on the function of a model, on the fit with data and on the aspects of a phenomenon that are modelled. Model users weigh the propositions entailed by a model and from this decide which of these propositions are crucial to the acceptance and continued use of the model. Thus, models represent phenomena when certain propositions they entail are true, but this alone does not exhaust the representational relationship. Therefore, the constraints that produce the choice of the relevant propositions in a model must also be examined and their analysis contributes to understanding the relationship between models and phenomena.

[1]  R. Harré The Principles Of Scientific Thinking , 1970 .

[2]  Margaret Morrison,et al.  Models as Mediators , 1999 .

[3]  R. Hughes Models and Representation , 1997, Philosophy of Science.

[4]  Margaret Morrison,et al.  Modelling nature : Between physics and the physical world , 1998 .

[5]  S. Kosslyn Image and mind , 1982 .

[6]  Maurice Ebison,et al.  Quantum Physics of Atoms, Molecules, Solids, Nuclei and Particles , 1975 .

[7]  James R. Griesemer,et al.  Material Models in Biology , 1990, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

[8]  David E. Kieras,et al.  The Role of a Mental Model in Learning to Operate a Device , 1990, Cogn. Sci..

[9]  Bas C. van Fraassen,et al.  The Scientific Image , 1980 .

[10]  N. Cartwright The dappled world : a study of the boundaries of science , 1999 .

[11]  Mauricio Suárez,et al.  Theories, Models, and Representations , 1999 .

[12]  Raymond T. Grontkowski Concepts of Science , 1970 .

[13]  Jan de Leeuw,et al.  MODELS OF DATA , 2000 .

[14]  M. Krampen The Mental Image , 1991 .

[15]  Philip N. Johnson-Laird,et al.  Mental Models in Cognitive Science , 1980, Cogn. Sci..

[16]  D. Bailer-Jones Modelling Extended Extragalactic Radio Sources , 2000 .

[17]  Physical Models and Biological Contexts , 1997, Philosophy of Science.

[18]  Margaret Morrison,et al.  Models as Mediators: Models as autonomous agents , 1999 .

[19]  S. Kosslyn Image and Brain: The Resolution of the Imagery Debate , 1994, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

[20]  Daniela M. Bailer-Jones,et al.  Creative Strategies Employed in Modelling: A Case Study , 1999 .

[21]  Ronald N. Giere,et al.  Science without laws , 1999 .

[22]  R. Harré VI—Metaphor, Model and Mechanism , 1960 .

[23]  S. Kosslyn Image and Brain , 1994 .

[24]  Stephan Hartmann,et al.  Models as a Tool for Theory Construction: Some Strategies of Preliminary Physics , 1995 .

[25]  Nancy Cartwright,et al.  The tool box of science: Tools for the building of models with a superconductivity example , 1995 .

[26]  Stephan Hartmann,et al.  Idealization in Quantum Field Theory , 1998 .

[27]  Ronald N. Giere,et al.  Using Models to Represent Reality , 1999 .

[28]  R. Young Surrogates and mappings: two kinds of conceptual models for interactive , 1983 .

[29]  Ernest H. Hutten THE ROLE OF MODELS IN PHYSICS* , 1953, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.