Justified True Belief Triggers False Recall of "Knowing"

Philosophers traditionally held that knowledge is justified true belief. Gettier (1963) challenged this view with thought experiments in which someone has a justified and true belief, but an element of luck is involved that disqualifies the belief from counting as knowledge. We examined laypeople’s concept of knowledge using a semantic integration paradigm modeled after that of Gentner (1981). Participants read stories in which a character ‘thought’ something was true. On a subsequent recall task, readers sometimes falsely recalled the verb ‘thought’ as ‘knew,’ implicitly indicating that the reader had attributed knowledge to the character. False recall of ‘knew’ occurred more frequently when the story described a justified true belief than an unjustified belief. Justified true belief triggered these recall errors even in a so-called “Gettier case”. The present findings suggest that semantic integration provides an empirical paradigm suitable for investigating lay notions about knowledge.

[1]  John D. Bransford,et al.  The abstraction of linguistic ideas , 1971 .

[2]  D. Gentner Integrating verb meanings into context , 1981 .

[3]  Thomas D. Cook,et al.  Subject effects in laboratory research: An examination of subject roles, demand characteristics, and valid inference. , 1972 .

[4]  J. Schaffer,et al.  Contrastive Knowledge Surveyed , 2012 .

[5]  N. Pinillos Knowledge, Experiments, and Practical Interests , 2012 .

[6]  John B. Black,et al.  The “soap opera” effect in story recall , 1979 .

[7]  Jonathan Waskan,et al.  Explanatory anti-psychologism overturned by lay and scientific case classifications , 2013, Synthese.

[8]  Jack B. Soll,et al.  Overconfidence: It Depends on How, What, and Whom You Ask. , 1999, Organizational behavior and human decision processes.

[9]  M. Tomasello,et al.  Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later , 2008, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[10]  Edmund L. Gettier Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? , 1963, Arguing About Knowledge.

[11]  O. Friedman,et al.  The folk conception of knowledge , 2012, Cognition.

[12]  D. Dooling,et al.  Intrusion of a thematic idea in retention of prose. , 1974 .

[13]  J. Sachs Recognition memory for syntactic and semantic aspects of connected discourse , 1967 .

[14]  Perry W. Thorndyke,et al.  The role of inferences in discourse comprehension , 1976 .

[15]  M. Orne On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications. , 1962 .

[16]  Brian K. Kooy Philosopher's Imprint , 2009 .

[17]  A. Kauppinen THE RISE AND FALL OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY , 2007 .

[18]  J. Deese On the prediction of occurrence of particular verbal intrusions in immediate recall. , 1959, Journal of experimental psychology.

[19]  Reid Hastie,et al.  Effects of Amount of Information on Judgment Accuracy and Confidence , 2008 .

[20]  Naomi Miyake,et al.  Proceedings of the Thirty-Fourth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society , 2012 .

[21]  Simon Cullen Survey-Driven Romanticism , 2010 .

[22]  Joshua Knobe,et al.  Experimental philosophy. , 2012, Annual review of psychology.

[23]  John Turri A Conspicuous Art: Putting Gettier to the Test , 2013 .

[24]  J. Weinberg,et al.  Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions , 2001 .

[25]  K. McDermott,et al.  Creating false memories: Remembering words not presented in lists. , 1995 .

[26]  Michael Isfort,et al.  Knowledge and Action , 2003, Nature.

[27]  S. Birch,et al.  When Knowledge Is a Curse , 2005 .

[28]  J. Livengood,et al.  The Folk Probably Don't Think What You Think They Think: Experiments on Causation by Absence , 2007 .

[29]  Paul W. Flagg Semantic Integration in Sentence Memory , 1976 .

[30]  E. Balint Memory and consciousness. , 1987, The International journal of psycho-analysis.

[31]  Valerie San Juan,et al.  Lay denial of knowledge for justified true beliefs , 2013, Cognition.