Dehumanization increases instrumental violence, but not moral violence

Significance To eliminate violence, we must understand the motives that drive it. Most theories assume that violence is motivated by instrumental gain or impulsiveness, and is restrained by moral inhibitions. In these frameworks, dehumanization breaks down moral inhibitions by reducing perceptions of victims as fellow human beings worthy of concern. However, we argue that much violence is actually motivated by moral sentiments, and that morally motivated perpetrators wish to harm fellow human beings. Across five experiments, we show that dehumanizing victims increases instrumental, but not moral, violence. This distinction, between instrumental violence enabled by dehumanization, and moral violence directed toward human victims, has important implications for understanding how morality and dehumanization interact with violence, and for informing violence reduction efforts worldwide. Across five experiments, we show that dehumanization—the act of perceiving victims as not completely human—increases instrumental, but not moral, violence. In attitude surveys, ascribing reduced capacities for cognitive, experiential, and emotional states to victims predicted support for practices where victims are harmed to achieve instrumental goals, including sweatshop labor, animal experimentation, and drone strikes that result in civilian casualties, but not practices where harm is perceived as morally righteous, including capital punishment, killing in war, and drone strikes that kill terrorists. In vignette experiments, using dehumanizing compared with humanizing language increased participants’ willingness to harm strangers for money, but not participants’ willingness to harm strangers for their immoral behavior. Participants also spontaneously dehumanized strangers when they imagined harming them for money, but not when they imagined harming them for their immoral behavior. Finally, participants humanized strangers who were low in humanity if they imagined harming them for immoral behavior, but not money, suggesting that morally motivated perpetrators may humanize victims to justify violence against them. Our findings indicate that dehumanization enables violence that perpetrators see as unethical, but instrumentally beneficial. In contrast, dehumanization does not contribute to moral violence because morally motivated perpetrators wish to harm complete human beings who are capable of deserving blame, experiencing suffering, and understanding its meaning.

[1]  A. Bandura,et al.  Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement in the Exercise of Moral Agency , 1996 .

[2]  Nicole Tausch,et al.  The Impact of Intergroup Emotions on Forgiveness in Northern Ireland , 2007 .

[3]  N. Haslam,et al.  Blaming, praising, and protecting our humanity: the implications of everyday dehumanization for judgments of moral status. , 2011, The British journal of social psychology.

[4]  YU Miao-miao,et al.  Crime as Social Control , 2007 .

[5]  N. Haslam,et al.  Dehumanization and infrahumanization. , 2014, Annual review of psychology.

[6]  A. A. Derefaka Archaeology and Culture History in the Central Niger Delta , 2006 .

[7]  N. Epley,et al.  Social connection enables dehumanization , 2012 .

[8]  Amy J. C. Cuddy,et al.  The BIAS map: behaviors from intergroup affect and stereotypes. , 2007, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[9]  Adrian F. Ward,et al.  The Harm-Made Mind , 2013, Psychological science.

[10]  Johannes Lang Questioning Dehumanization: Intersubjective Dimensions of Violence in the Nazi Concentration and Death Camps , 2010, Holocaust and genocide studies.

[11]  N. Haslam,et al.  The Roles of Dehumanization and Moral Outrage in Retributive Justice , 2013, PloS one.

[12]  B. Leidner,et al.  Dehumanization, Retributive and Restorative Justice, and Aggressive Versus Diplomatic Intergroup Conflict Resolution Strategies , 2013, Personality & social psychology bulletin.

[13]  Susan V. Opotow Moral Exclusion and Injustice: An Introduction , 1990 .

[14]  Kurt Gray,et al.  Mind Perception Is the Essence of Morality , 2012, Psychological inquiry.

[15]  Clark McCauley,et al.  Threat, Dehumanization, and Support for Retaliatory Aggressive Policies in Asymmetric Conflict , 2008 .

[16]  S. Fiske,et al.  Dehumanizing the Lowest of the Low , 2006, Psychological science.

[17]  J. Gert,et al.  Humanism: A Critique , 2016 .

[18]  D. Smith Less Than Human: Why We Demean, Enslave, and Exterminate Others , 2011 .

[19]  Kurt Gray,et al.  The Unifying Moral Dyad , 2015, Personality & social psychology bulletin.

[20]  Jack Katz,et al.  Seductions of crime : moral and sensual attractions in doing evil , 1989 .

[21]  A. Fiske,et al.  Moral psychology is relationship regulation: moral motives for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportionality. , 2011, Psychological review.

[22]  J. Katz,et al.  Seductions of Crime: Moral and Sensual Attractions in Doing Evil. , 1990 .

[23]  C A Anderson,et al.  Is it time to pull the plug on the hostile versus instrumental aggression dichotomy? , 2001, Psychological review.

[24]  R. Boyd,et al.  The evolution of altruistic punishment , 2003, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.

[25]  A. Memmi The Colonizer and the Colonized , 1957 .

[26]  Ervin Staub,et al.  The roots of evil : the origins of genocide and other group violence , 1990 .

[27]  G. Ramsay Dehumanisation in religious and sectarian violence: the case of Islamic State , 2016 .

[28]  Michael D. Buhrmester,et al.  Amazon's Mechanical Turk , 2011, Perspectives on psychological science : a journal of the Association for Psychological Science.

[29]  N. Haslam,et al.  More human than you: attributing humanness to self and others. , 2005, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[30]  R. Duff,et al.  Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability: Philosophy of Action and the Criminal Law , 1990 .

[31]  B. Maxwell,et al.  The better angels of our nature: why violence has declined , 2013 .

[32]  Martha Craven Nussbaum,et al.  Sex and Social Justice , 2000 .

[33]  G. Viki,et al.  Dehumanization and self-reported proclivity to torture prisoners of war. , 2013 .

[34]  M. Khamitov,et al.  Perceiving the agency of harmful agents: A test of dehumanization versus moral typecasting accounts , 2016, Cognition.

[35]  John Mikhail,et al.  Universal moral grammar: theory, evidence and the future , 2007, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[36]  Herbert G. Kelman Violence without Moral Restraint: Reflections on the Dehumanization of Victims and Victimizers , 1973 .

[37]  Adam Waytz,et al.  Social Cognition Unbound , 2010, Current directions in psychological science.

[38]  Phillip Atiba Goff,et al.  Not yet human: implicit knowledge, historical dehumanization, and contemporary consequences. , 2008, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[39]  Mina Cikara,et al.  On the wrong side of the trolley track: neural correlates of relative social valuation. , 2010, Social cognitive and affective neuroscience.

[40]  Scott Atran,et al.  Talking to the Enemy: Faith, Brotherhood, and the (Un)Making of Terrorists , 2010 .

[41]  Richard B. Felson,et al.  Violence, aggression & coercive actions , 1994 .

[42]  Delfina Cabrera En torno a la criminología cultural. Nota sobre Jack Katz: “Seductions of crime: moral and sensual attractions in doing evil”, Basic Books, New York, 1988 , 2016 .

[43]  M. Gollwitzer,et al.  Get the Message , 2014, Personality & social psychology bulletin.

[44]  Avishai Margalit,et al.  The Ethics of Memory , 2002 .

[45]  E. Turiel,et al.  The Development of Social Knowledge: Morality and Convention , 1983 .

[46]  N. Schwarz Self-reports: How the questions shape the answers. , 1999 .

[47]  D. Wegner,et al.  Dimensions of Mind Perception , 2007, Science.

[48]  Anthony Appiah,et al.  Experiments in Ethics , 2008 .

[49]  T. Wheatley,et al.  Are moral judgments unified? , 2014 .

[50]  Emile G. Bruneau,et al.  The ascent of man: Theoretical and empirical evidence for blatant dehumanization. , 2015, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[51]  Douglas A. Pryer Less Than Human: Why We Demean, Enslave, and Exterminate Others , 2012 .

[52]  N. Haslam Dehumanization: An Integrative Review , 2006, Personality and social psychology review : an official journal of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc.

[53]  A. Bandura Moral Disengagement in the Perpetration of Inhumanities , 1999, Personality and social psychology review : an official journal of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc.

[54]  C. Anderson,et al.  Human Aggression , 1989, Annual review of psychology.

[55]  Edison J. Trickett,et al.  Thinking It Through: An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy , 2003 .

[56]  A. Fiske,et al.  Virtuous Violence: Hurting and Killing to Create, Sustain, End, and Honor Social Relationships , 2014 .

[57]  Jeroen Vaes,et al.  Psychological essentialism and the differential attribution of uniquely human emotions to ingroups and outgroups , 2001 .

[58]  Michael I. Norton,et al.  Aid in the Aftermath of Hurricane Katrina: Inferences of Secondary Emotions and Intergroup Helping , 2007 .

[59]  Kurt Gray,et al.  Moral typecasting: divergent perceptions of moral agents and moral patients. , 2009, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[60]  S. Fiske From Dehumanization and Objectification to Rehumanization , 2009, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences.

[61]  Roberto González,et al.  What do I Care? Perceived Ingroup Responsibility and Dehumanization as Predictors of Empathy Felt for the Victim Group , 2009 .

[62]  B. Reviews,et al.  Inhuman Bondage: The Rise and Fall of Slavery in the New World , 2008 .

[63]  D. Smith Paradoxes of Dehumanization , 2016 .

[64]  Laurie A. Rudman,et al.  Of Animals and Objects , 2012, Personality & social psychology bulletin.