Should the Model for Risk‐Informed Regulation be Game Theory Rather than Decision Theory?

Risk analysts frequently view the regulation of risks as being largely a matter of decision theory. According to this view, risk analysis methods provide information on the likelihood and severity of various possible outcomes; this information should then be assessed using a decision-theoretic approach (such as cost/benefit analysis) to determine whether the risks are acceptable, and whether additional regulation is warranted. However, this view ignores the fact that in many industries (particularly industries that are technologically sophisticated and employ specialized risk and safety experts), risk analyses may be done by regulated firms, not by the regulator. Moreover, those firms may have more knowledge about the levels of safety at their own facilities than the regulator does. This creates a situation in which the regulated firm has both the opportunity-and often also the motive-to provide inaccurate (in particular, favorably biased) risk information to the regulator, and hence the regulator has reason to doubt the accuracy of the risk information provided by regulated parties. Researchers have argued that decision theory is capable of dealing with many such strategic interactions as well as game theory can. This is especially true in two-player, two-stage games in which the follower has a unique best strategy in response to the leader's strategy, as appears to be the case in the situation analyzed in this article. However, even in such cases, we agree with Cox that game-theoretic methods and concepts can still be useful. In particular, the tools of mechanism design, and especially the revelation principle, can simplify the analysis of such games because the revelation principle provides rigorous assurance that it is sufficient to analyze only games in which licensees truthfully report their risk levels, making the problem more manageable. Without that, it would generally be necessary to consider much more complicated forms of strategic behavior (including deception), to identify optimal regulatory strategies. Therefore, we believe that the types of regulatory interactions analyzed in this article are better modeled using game theory rather than decision theory. In particular, the goals of this article are to review the relevant literature in game theory and regulatory economics (to stimulate interest in this area among risk analysts), and to present illustrative results showing how the application of game theory can provide useful insights into the theory and practice of risk-informed regulation.

[1]  Kathleen Segerson,et al.  On the Role of Fines as an Environmental Enforcement Tool , 1998 .

[2]  J. P. Brown Toward an Economic Theory of Liability , 1973, The Journal of Legal Studies.

[3]  John Kambhu,et al.  Direct controls and incentives systems of regulation , 1990 .

[4]  Paul B. Downing,et al.  ENFORCING POLLUTION CONTROL LAWS IN THE U.S. , 1982 .

[5]  Martin Walker,et al.  Random wastes, imperfect monitoring and environmental quality standards , 1983 .

[6]  Paul R. Kleindorfer,et al.  Informational Regulation of Environmental Risks , 1998 .

[7]  Clifford S. Russell,et al.  Enforcing Pollution Control Laws , 1986 .

[8]  Anthony Heyes,et al.  Implementing Environmental Regulation: Enforcement and Compliance , 2000 .

[9]  A. Malik,et al.  Self-Reporting and the Design of Policies for Regulating Stochastic Pollution , 1993 .

[10]  Vicki M. Bier,et al.  Defaults and Incentives in Risk-Informed Regulation , 1999 .

[11]  R. Innes Violator Avoidance Activities and Self‐Reporting in Optimal Law Enforcement , 2001 .

[12]  Joseph Greenberg,et al.  Avoiding tax avoidance: A (repeated) game-theoretic approach , 1984 .

[13]  Peter Cleary Yeager,et al.  The limits of law: Bibliography , 1991 .

[14]  W. Harrington,et al.  A reconsideration of enforcement leverage when penalties are restricted , 1991 .

[15]  Robert Innes,et al.  Remediation and self-reporting in optimal law enforcement , 1999 .

[16]  J. Harford Measurement error and state-dependent pollution control enforcement , 1991 .

[17]  A. Heyes Environmental enforcement when ‘inspectability’ is endogenous: A model with overshooting properties , 1994 .

[18]  Howard Kunreuther,et al.  Managing Environmental Risk Through Insurance , 1997 .

[19]  D. Okrent,et al.  Development of quantitative risk acceptance criteria , 1981 .

[20]  Jerry R. Green On the Optimal Structure of Liability Laws , 1976 .

[21]  Charles D. Kolstad,et al.  Ex Post Liability for Harm vs. Ex Ante Safety Regulation: Substitutes or Complements? , 1990 .

[22]  Donald Wittman,et al.  Prior Regulation versus Post Liability: The Choice between Input and Output Monitoring , 1977, The Journal of Legal Studies.

[23]  P. Downing Bargaining in pollution control. , 1983, Policy studies journal: the journal of the Policy Studies Organization.

[24]  Robert Innes,et al.  Self‐Policing and Optimal Law Enforcement When Violator Remediation is Valuable , 1999, Journal of Political Economy.

[25]  Leslie M. Marx,et al.  Exploring Relations between Decision Analysis and Game Theory , 2007, Decis. Anal..

[26]  Violation-minimizing fine schedules , 1987 .

[27]  I. Meilijson,et al.  Incentive generating state dependent penalty system: The case of income tax evasion , 1982 .

[28]  J. Harford,et al.  Initial and Continuing Compliance and the Trade-Off between Monitoring and Control Cost☆ , 2000 .

[29]  Steven Shavell,et al.  A MODEL OF THE OPTIMAL USE OF LIABILITY AND SAFETY REGULATION , 1984 .

[30]  J. Shogren,et al.  Challenging the enforcement of environmental regulation , 1994 .

[31]  J. Kambhu Regulatory standards, noncompliance and enforcement , 1989 .

[32]  Steven Shavell,et al.  Liability and the Incentive to Obtain Information about Risk , 1992, The Journal of Legal Studies.

[33]  Eric A. Helland The Enforcement of Pollution Control Laws: Inspections, Violations, and Self-Reporting , 1998, Review of Economics and Statistics.

[34]  S. Breyer Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation , 1993 .

[35]  John D. Graham,et al.  Reform of risk regulation: Achieving more protection at less cost , 1995 .

[36]  Scott M. Gilpatric,et al.  Regulation with Direct Benefits of Information Disclosure and Imperfect Monitoring , 2008 .

[37]  John T. Scholz Cooperation, Deterrence, and the Ecology of Regulatory Enforcement , 1984 .

[38]  Winston Harrington,et al.  Enforcement leverage when penalties are restricted , 1988 .

[39]  Paul R. Kleindorfer,et al.  Regulatory Economics: Twenty Years of Progress? , 2002 .

[40]  M. Raymond Regulatory Compliance with Costly and Uncertain Litigation , 2004 .

[41]  Sarah Stafford Self-Policing in a Targeted Enforcement Regime , 2008 .

[42]  A. Heyes Cutting environmental penalties to protect the environment , 1996 .

[43]  Jr. Louis Anthony Cox,et al.  Game Theory and Risk Analysis , 2009 .

[44]  W. Wagner,et al.  Choosing ignorance in the manufacture of toxic products. , 1997, Cornell law review.

[45]  Sarah L. Stafford,et al.  Should you turn yourself in? The consequences of environmental self-policing , 2007 .

[46]  H C Kunreuther,et al.  Compliance strategies and regulatory effectiveness of performance-based regulation of chemical accident risks. , 1998, Risk analysis : an official publication of the Society for Risk Analysis.

[47]  J. Applegate The Perils of Unreasonable Risk: Information, Regulatory Policy, and Toxic Substances Control , 1991 .

[48]  John Livernois,et al.  Truth or consequences: Enforcing pollution standards with self-reporting , 1999 .