Commentary on Hey and Kimmelman

In classical randomized controlled trials (RCTs), randomization probabilities remain fixed throughout the duration of the study. However, in any trial that ultimately shows one arm to be superior, data will at some point provide mounting though not yet definitive evidence in favor of the better performing arm. In trials with serious, irreversible outcomes, a data monitoring committee is typically charged with regular review of emerging data and with making recommendations about early termination if extreme effects are seen. Still, commentators struggle over the necessity of randomizing participants to the arm that appears inferior based on emerging data. Some investigators and ethicists have advocated response-adaptive over fixed randomization to maximize the proportion of participants assigned to the better performing arm. In this issue of Clinical Trials, Hey and Kimmelman advocate a ‘‘rebuttable presumption’’ against adaptive randomization, at least in the setting of two-arm trials comparing a novel intervention to a control. They offer a range of arguments to buttress their conclusion. First, they contend that advocates of adaptive randomization overestimate the likelihood and magnitude of benefits that it offers participants. Studies may adjust randomization probabilities based on surrogate endpoints that don’t correlate with clinical benefit; clinical endpoints may be too delayed to allow timely adjustment; the magnitude of incremental benefit associated with novel therapies is often small; and the complexities of implementing adaptive designs may preclude their use in most settings. Second, they note that because 1:1 randomization represents the most efficient allocation ratio, adaptive trials are likely to take longer than conventional trials, require more participants, or both. Third, they claim that adaptive trials encourage rather than dispel participants’ unrealistic expectations about the benefits of experimental therapies, thereby failing to advance, or even undermining, informed consent. Finally, they note that changes over time in the proportions of individuals assigned to each arm might interact with temporal trends in background conditions or participant characteristics to threaten the validity of the trial. In drawing their measured conclusion against the use of adaptive randomization, Hey and Kimmelman do not conclude that such trials are unethical. In this, they are surely correct. But adaptive trials do involve important tradeoffs among core scientific and ethical values that investigators must weigh as they consider alternative research designs. A widely recognized framework holds that ethical research fulfills seven criteria: social value, scientific validity, fair subject selection, favorable benefit/risk ratio, independent review, informed consent and respect for participants. Three of these criteria—scientific validity, favorable benefit/risk ratio and informed consent—are particularly relevant to assessing adaptive designs. Scientific validity is a basic condition for ethical research. Research aims to produce generalizable knowledge; studies that are unlikely to permit valid conclusions cannot justify exposing participants to risk. In addition, the prospect of valid conclusions is what legitimizes the use of resources in the research, including money, facilities, personnel and—most important— participants. The main challenge to validity noted by Hey and Kimmelman is the possibility that subjects who enter later in the trial may differ systematically— for example, by prognosis—from those who enter earlier. Adjustment for all known and unknown factors associated with prognosis would eliminate this problem, but such adjustment is generally impossible. Thus, imbalanced allocation could lead to systematic between-group differences in prognosis that would bias the analysis of the trial. In addition to this and other challenges to validity that Hey and Kimmelman identify, open-label adaptive trials face two further threats. First, most phase III randomized trials strictly maintain the confidentiality of

[1]  J. Kimmelman,et al.  Are outcome-adaptive allocation trials ethical? , 2015, Clinical trials.

[2]  S. Saxman Ethical Considerations for Outcome‐Adaptive Trial Designs: A Clinical Researcher's Perspective , 2015, Bioethics.

[3]  Michael Hay,et al.  Clinical development success rates for investigational drugs , 2014, Nature Biotechnology.

[4]  J. Kimmelman,et al.  The questionable use of unequal allocation in confirmatory trials , 2014, Neurology.

[5]  W. Meurer,et al.  Can Response-Adaptive Randomization Increase Participation in Acute Stroke Trials? , 2013, Stroke.

[6]  Roger J Lewis,et al.  Response‐adaptive decision‐theoretic trial design: operating characteristics and ethics , 2013, Statistics in medicine.

[7]  Ambuj Kumar,et al.  Medical research: Trial unpredictability yields predictable therapy gains , 2013, Nature.

[8]  Z. Estrov,et al.  Randomized open-label phase II study of decitabine in patients with low- or intermediate-risk myelodysplastic syndromes. , 2013, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[9]  Brenda Gaydos,et al.  Application of Adaptive Design Methodology in Development of a Long-Acting Glucagon-like Peptide-1 Analog (Dulaglutide): Statistical Design and Simulations , 2012, Journal of diabetes science and technology.

[10]  D. Berry,et al.  Bayesian adaptive trial design in acute heart failure syndromes: moving beyond the mega trial. , 2012, American heart journal.

[11]  G. Yin,et al.  Worth Adapting? Revisiting the Usefulness of Outcome-Adaptive Randomization , 2012, Clinical Cancer Research.

[12]  Johannes J M van Delden,et al.  Adaptive trials in clinical research: scientific and ethical issues to consider. , 2012, JAMA.

[13]  Roger J Lewis,et al.  Adaptive clinical trials: a partial remedy for the therapeutic misconception? , 2012, JAMA.

[14]  D. Berry Adaptive clinical trials in oncology , 2012, Nature Reviews Clinical Oncology.

[15]  Dalene Stangl,et al.  Celebrating 70: An Interview with Don Berry , 2012, 1203.5668.

[16]  Edward S. Kim,et al.  The BATTLE trial: personalizing therapy for lung cancer. , 2011, Cancer discovery.

[17]  W. Chiong Equipoise and the dilemma of randomized clinical trials. , 2011, The New England journal of medicine.

[18]  B. Freidlin,et al.  Outcome--adaptive randomization: is it useful? , 2011, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[19]  D. Berry Adaptive clinical trials: the promise and the caution. , 2011, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[20]  Michael Krams,et al.  A Bayesian dose-finding trial with adaptive dose expansion to flexibly assess efficacy and safety of an investigational drug , 2010, Clinical trials.

[21]  D. Berry,et al.  I‐SPY 2: An Adaptive Breast Cancer Trial Design in the Setting of Neoadjuvant Chemotherapy , 2009, Clinical pharmacology and therapeutics.

[22]  Diane D. Liu,et al.  Bayesian clinical trials at the University of Texas M. D. Anderson Cancer Center , 2009, Clinical trials.

[23]  A. London Clinical Equipoise: Foundational Requirement or Fundamental Error? , 2009 .

[24]  P. Thall,et al.  Randomized phase II study of gemcitabine and docetaxel compared with gemcitabine alone in patients with metastatic soft tissue sarcomas: results of sarcoma alliance for research through collaboration study 002 [corrected]. , 2007, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[25]  Paul Gallo,et al.  Adaptive Dose-Response Studies , 2006 .

[26]  J C Dumville,et al.  The use of unequal randomisation ratios in clinical trials: a review. , 2006, Contemporary clinical trials.

[27]  G. Pond,et al.  Comparison of outcomes of phase II studies and subsequent randomized control studies using identical chemotherapeutic regimens. , 2005, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[28]  C. Heilig,et al.  A critical history of individual and collective ethics in the lineage of Lellouch and Schwartz , 2005, Clinical trials.

[29]  C. Weijer,et al.  When are research risks reasonable in relation to anticipated benefits? , 2004, Nature Medicine.

[30]  D. Berry Bayesian Statistics and the Efficiency and Ethics of Clinical Trials , 2004 .

[31]  D. Berry,et al.  Choosing sample size for a clinical trial using decision analysis , 2003 .

[32]  Dezheng Huo,et al.  A group sequential, response-adaptive design for randomized clinical trials. , 2003, Controlled clinical trials.

[33]  D. Berry,et al.  Adaptive randomized study of idarubicin and cytarabine versus troxacitabine and cytarabine versus troxacitabine and idarubicin in untreated patients 50 years or older with adverse karyotype acute myeloid leukemia. , 2003, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[34]  C. Grady,et al.  Misunderstanding in clinical research: distinguishing therapeutic misconception, therapeutic misestimation, and therapeutic optimism. , 2003, IRB.

[35]  David L. DeMets,et al.  Data Monitoring Committees in Clinical Trials: A Practical Perspective , 2002 .

[36]  David L. DeMets,et al.  Data Monitoring Committees in Clinical Trials , 2002 .

[37]  C. Grady,et al.  What makes clinical research ethical? , 2000, JAMA.

[38]  C. Palmer,et al.  Ethics and Practice , 1999 .

[39]  W F Rosenberger,et al.  Ethics and practice: alternative designs for phase III randomized clinical trials. , 1997, Controlled clinical trials.

[40]  D. Berry,et al.  Adaptive assignment versus balanced randomization in clinical trials: a decision analysis. , 1995, Statistics in medicine.

[41]  J M Lachin,et al.  The use of response-adaptive designs in clinical trials. , 1993, Controlled clinical trials.

[42]  J. O'fallon,et al.  Policies for study monitoring and interim reporting of results. , 1987, Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology.

[43]  P S Appelbaum,et al.  False hopes and best data: consent to research and the therapeutic misconception. , 1987, The Hastings Center report.

[44]  D. Marquis,et al.  Leaving therapy to chance. , 1983, The Hastings Center report.

[45]  D A Berry,et al.  Statistical inference and the design of clinical trials. , 1980, Biomedicine / [publiee pour l'A.A.I.C.I.G.].

[46]  Donald A. Berry,et al.  Modified Two-Armed Bandit Strategies for Certain Clinical Trials , 1978 .

[47]  J. Lellouch,et al.  L'essai therapeutique: ethique individuelle ou ethique collective? , 1971 .

[48]  F. Crick,et al.  DEPARTMENT of Health, Education, and Welfare. , 1953, California medicine.