Ethical challenges in genotype-driven research recruitment.

Many genetic and genomic studies are conducted using a phenotype-driven approach: Cases and controls are identified based on the presence or absence of a particular condition and analyses are undertaken to identify gene variants associated with that condition. The inverse—a genotype-driven approach—is receiving increasing attention as another powerful research tool. In this setting, investigators use existing study populations for which genotype or complete sequence data are available to identify cases and controls based on the presence or absence of a particular gene variant. Participants are then recontacted for recruitment into follow-up studies involving in-depth phenotyping to understand the relationship between observable traits and the gene variant of interest. One driver for this framework is the genetics community's increasing focus on rarer gene variants that exert a large effect on risk for common diseases. Enabling such a “bottom-up” approach to identifying and recruiting participants for follow-up studies could significantly advance the pace of genomic research on the functional significance of human genetic variation (McGuire and McGuire 2008). Genotype-driven recruitment, however, presents considerable ethical challenges. It is inextricably linked to the complex and much-debated issue of disclosing individual research results to participants: When individuals are recontacted, what if anything should they be told about the genotype that led to their being recontacted? There is a fundamental tension between avoiding the disclosure of potentially unwanted and uncertain information, and avoiding deception when explaining to prospective participants the purpose of the research and why they have been identified as eligible to participate. To resolve this tension, McGuire and McGuire (2008) suggested that, when recontacted, participants should be told that the follow-up study is genotype-driven and what that means, what the genotype and biological pathway of interest is, that half of the participants are controls without the targeted gene variants, and that an invitation to participate is not contingent on the presence of any known phenotype. Here, we report our experiences and participants' reactions when we implemented a similar approach.

[1]  L. Beskow Considering the Nature of Individual Research Results , 2006, The American journal of bioethics : AJOB.

[2]  L. Beskow,et al.  Informed Consent for Biorepositories: Assessing Prospective Participants' Understanding and Opinions , 2008, Cancer Epidemiology Biomarkers & Prevention.

[3]  Richard M Myers,et al.  Population analysis of large copy number variants and hotspots of human genetic disease. , 2009, American journal of human genetics.

[4]  Gail Javitt,et al.  ASHG Statement* on Direct-to-Consumer Genetic Testing in the United States , 2007, Obstetrics and gynecology.

[5]  J. Robert,et al.  Duty to disclose what? Querying the putative obligation to return research results to participants , 2008, Journal of Medical Ethics.

[6]  Amy L McGuire,et al.  Don't throw the baby out with the bathwater: enabling a bottom-up approach in genome-wide association studies. , 2008, Genome research.

[7]  C. Baker,et al.  Recurrent rearrangements of chromosome 1q21.1 and variable pediatric phenotypes. , 2008, The New England journal of medicine.

[8]  Gail P Jarvik,et al.  Reporting genetic results in research studies: Summary and recommendations of an NHLBI working group , 2006, American journal of medical genetics. Part A.

[9]  A. van Haeringen,et al.  Interstitial deletion of 6q without phenotypic effect , 2007, American journal of medical genetics. Part A.

[10]  H. Mefford,et al.  Recurrent reciprocal deletions and duplications of 16p13.11: the deletion is a risk factor for MR/MCA while the duplication may be a rare benign variant , 2008, Journal of Medical Genetics.

[11]  Leslie A. Meltzer Undesirable Implications of Disclosing Individual Genetic Results to Research Participants , 2006, The American journal of bioethics : AJOB.

[12]  A 10.7 Mb interstitial deletion of 13q21 without phenotypic effect defines a further non‐pathogenic euchromatic variant , 2008, American journal of medical genetics. Part A.

[13]  I. Scheffer,et al.  Multicentre search for genetic susceptibility loci in sporadic epilepsy syndrome and seizure types: a case-control study , 2007, The Lancet Neurology.

[14]  C. Fernandez Public Expectations for Return of Results—Time to Stop Being Paternalistic? , 2008, The American journal of bioethics : AJOB.

[15]  B. Wilfond,et al.  Disclosing Individual Genetic Results to Research Participants , 2006, The American journal of bioethics : AJOB.

[16]  Susanne B Haga,et al.  Ethical, legal, and social implications of biobanks for genetics research. , 2008, Advances in genetics.

[17]  E. Clayton,et al.  Implications of disclosing individual results of clinical research. , 2006, JAMA.

[18]  M. W. Foster,et al.  Clinical Utility and Full Disclosure of Genetic Results to Research Participants , 2006, The American journal of bioethics : AJOB.

[19]  F. Miller,et al.  Disclosing individual results of clinical research: implications of respect for participants. , 2005, JAMA.

[20]  David B. Goldstein,et al.  A Genome-Wide Investigation of SNPs and CNVs in Schizophrenia , 2009, PLoS genetics.

[21]  Jeremy Sugarman,et al.  Ethical issues in identifying and recruiting participants for familial genetic research , 2004, American journal of medical genetics. Part A.

[22]  Thomas W. Mühleisen,et al.  Large recurrent microdeletions associated with schizophrenia , 2008, Nature.

[23]  Michael R. Johnson,et al.  Rare deletions at 16p13.11 predispose to a diverse spectrum of sporadic epilepsy syndromes. , 2010, American journal of human genetics.