Obligatory Irrelevance and the Computation of Ignorance Inferences

The standard grammatical theory of scalar implicature, as envisioned by Chierchia (2004), Fox (2007), and Chierchia, Fox, and Spector (2012), posits that scalar implicatures are derived in grammar, as a matter semantics, rather than pragmatically, as an implicature rooted in Grice’s maxim of quantity. Ignorance inferences, by contrast, e.g. those associated with plain disjunctive sentences, are derived pragmatically, as quantity implicatures. More generally, the standard theory predicts that for any utterance S and any relevant proposition φ which isn’t entailed, and whose negation isn’t entailed, by S, S gives rise to an inference of speaker ignorance about φ. We argue that this prediction is wrong: it fails to explain the contrast in ignorance inferences associated with at least (which obligatorily implies ignorance) vs. more than (which doesn’t) (Geurts and Nouwen 2007; Nouwen 2010, 2015). The problem is that, without stipulating restrictions on which propositions are relevant, the theory overgenerates ignorance inferences across the board. We argue that the solution is to close relevance under belief (if φ is relevant, then it’s also relevant whether the speaker believes φ). This move has the effect that ignorance inferences, like scalar implicatures, can only be derived in grammar, via a covert belief operator of the sort proposed by Meyer (2013) and discussed further by Fox (2016). The maxim of quantity, we show, then no longer enriches the meaning of an utterance, per se, but rather acts as a filter on what can be relevant in an utterance context. In particular, certain alternatives (of certain utterances) are shown to be incapable of being relevant in any context where the maxim of quantity is active — a property we dub obligatory irrelevance. We argue that obligatory irrelevance provides the key to understanding the contrast in ignorance inferences exhibited by at least vs. more than. We also argue that translating our proposal into neo-Gricean terms, if at all possible, would yield a conceptually less appealing and empirically less adequate theory.

[1]  D. Fox Free Choice and the Theory of Scalar Implicatures , 2007 .

[2]  M. Krifka At least some Determiners aren ’ t Determiners , 1999 .

[3]  G. Chierchia,et al.  Logic in Grammar: Polarity, Free Choice, and Intervention , 2013 .

[4]  Annett Baier,et al.  Logic In Grammar Polarity Free Choice And Intervention , 2016 .

[5]  G. Chierchia,et al.  Broaden Your Views: Implicatures of Domain Widening and the Logicality of Language , 2006, Linguistic Inquiry.

[6]  Noah Constant English rise-fall-rise: a study in the semantics and pragmatics of intonation , 2012 .

[7]  K. Fintel,et al.  Exceptive constructions , 1993 .

[8]  Laurence R. Horn,et al.  On the semantic properties of logical operators in english' reproduced by the indiana university lin , 1972 .

[9]  Chris Kennedy From Grammar to Meaning: A scalar semantics for scalar readings of number words , 2013 .

[10]  R. Nouwen Modified Numerals: the Epistemic Effect∗ , 2013 .

[11]  Manfred Krifka,et al.  Superlative Quantifiers as Modifiers of Meta-Speech Acts , 2010 .

[12]  B. Geurts,et al.  At least et al: The semantic of scalar modifiers , 2007 .

[13]  Jaakko Hintikka,et al.  Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. , 1965 .

[14]  Giorgio Magri A theory of individual-level predicates based on blind mandatory scalar implicatures , 2009 .

[15]  Uli Sauerland,et al.  Scalar Implicatures in Complex Sentences , 2004 .

[16]  Daniel Büring,et al.  The Least at least Can Do , 2008 .

[17]  David Liebesman Counting as a Type of Measuring , 2016 .

[18]  Danny Fox,et al.  The universal density of measurement , 2007 .

[19]  Siobhan Chapman Logic and Conversation , 2005 .

[20]  Christopher Kennedy A "de-Fregean" semantics (and neo-Gricean pragmatics) for modified and unmodified numerals , 2015 .

[21]  Julia Hirschberg,et al.  Implicating Uncertainty: The Pragmatics of Fall-Rise Intonation , 1985 .

[22]  Yo Matsumoto The conversational condition on horn scales , 1995 .

[23]  Tue Trinh,et al.  Keeping it simple , 2018, Natural Language Semantics.

[24]  Eric Swanson,et al.  Structurally defined alternatives and lexicalizations of XOR , 2010 .

[25]  Nathan Klinedinst,et al.  The symmetry problem: current theories and prospects , 2018 .

[26]  Bernhard Schwarz,et al.  Consistency preservation in Quantity implicature: The case of at least , 2016 .

[27]  G. Chierchia,et al.  Scalar implicature as a grammatical phenomenon , 2012 .

[28]  Andreas Haida,et al.  Constraining the derivation of alternatives , 2015 .

[29]  M. Westera Exhaustivity and intonation: a unified theory , 2017 .

[30]  Clemens Mayr From Grammar to Meaning: Implicatures of modified numerals , 2013 .

[31]  Doris Penka,et al.  'At most' at last , 2014 .

[32]  D. Fox Cancelling the Maxim of Quantity: Another challenge for a Gricean theory of Scalar Implicatures , 2014 .

[33]  Manfred Krifka,et al.  Superlative quantifiers and meta-speech acts , 2014 .

[34]  Elizabeth Coppock,et al.  Raising and resolving issues with scalar modifiers , 2013 .

[35]  D. Fox,et al.  On the characterization of alternatives , 2011 .

[36]  Jonathan Evans,et al.  Human Reasoning: The Psychology Of Deduction , 1993 .