Taking into Account the Strength of an Alternative Hypothesis

A common phenomenon in judgment under uncertainty is that alternative hypotheses are underweighted or ignored. This article addresses when and how the strength of the alternative is taken into account when there are 2 hypotheses. A learning manipulation was used to invoke 2 representations of 2 illnesses in a medical diagnosis task. One representation tended to lead to consideration of the alternative when, for example, requesting new information, reporting confidence, and making diagnoses. The other representation tended to result in ignoring or underweighting the alternative, but a simple change in how confidence was probed increased consideration of the alternative. Costs and benefits of each representation are discussed.

[1]  Yaacov Trope,et al.  Information-gathering strategies in hypothesis-testing , 1983 .

[2]  C. Mckenzie The Accuracy of Intuitive Judgment Strategies: Covariation Assessment and Bayesian Inference , 1994, Cognitive Psychology.

[3]  Richard P. Larrick,et al.  When one cause casts doubt on another: A normative analysis of discounting in causal attribution. , 1995 .

[4]  R. Hogarth,et al.  Order effects in belief updating: The belief-adjustment model , 1992, Cognitive Psychology.

[5]  Lori Robinson Van Wallendael The quest for limits on noncomplementarity in opinion revision , 1989 .

[6]  Jonathan S. Evans,et al.  Bias in human reasoning , 1990 .

[7]  Martin Edman The Probable and the Provable , 1980 .

[8]  Reid Hastie,et al.  Revision of beliefs when a hypothesis is eliminated from consideration. , 1985 .

[9]  David L. Ronis,et al.  Components of probability judgment accuracy: Individual consistency and effects of subject matter and assessment method. , 1987 .

[10]  B. Fischhoff,et al.  Reasons for confidence. , 1980 .

[11]  M. Zuckerman,et al.  Hypothesis confirmation: The joint effect of positive test strategy and acquiescence response set. , 1995 .

[12]  Reid Hastie,et al.  Tracing the footsteps of Sherlock Holmes: Cognitive representations of hypothesis testing , 1990, Memory & cognition.

[13]  B. Fischhoff,et al.  Hypothesis Evaluation from a Bayesian Perspective. , 1983 .

[14]  H Garavan,et al.  On people’s understanding of the diagnostic implications of probabilistic data , 1996, Memory & cognition.

[15]  Yaacov Trope,et al.  People's Strategies for Testing Hypotheses about Another's Personality: Confirmatory or Diagnostic? , 1984 .

[16]  Yaacov Trope,et al.  The questions lay interviewers ask , 1984 .

[17]  A. Tversky,et al.  On the study of statistical intuitions , 1982, Cognition.

[18]  R. Sternberg,et al.  Evaluation of evidence in causal inference. , 1981 .

[19]  Peter Whalley,et al.  The Supra-Additivity of Subjective Probability , 1983 .

[20]  R. Hogarth,et al.  Ambiguity and Uncertainty in Probabilistic Inference. , 1985 .

[21]  Yaacov Trope,et al.  Sensitivity to alternatives in social hypothesis-testing ☆ , 1987 .

[22]  R. Hastie,et al.  Hindsight: Biased judgments of past events after the outcomes are known. , 1990 .

[23]  G. Gigerenzer,et al.  Probabilistic mental models: a Brunswikian theory of confidence. , 1991, Psychological review.

[24]  G. Gigerenzer Why the distinction between single-event probabilities and frequencies is important for psychology (and vice versa). , 1994 .

[25]  Baruch Fischhoff,et al.  Diagnosticity and pseudodiagnosticity. , 1983 .

[26]  Robert L. Goldstone Isolated and interrelated concepts , 1996, Memory & cognition.

[27]  H. Arkes,et al.  Two methods of reducing overconfidence , 1987 .

[28]  G. Gigerenzer,et al.  Cognition as Intuitive Statistics , 1987 .

[29]  A. Tversky,et al.  Support theory: A nonextensional representation of subjective probability. , 1994 .

[30]  D. Medin,et al.  Similarity and Alignment in Choice , 1995 .

[31]  J. Klayman,et al.  Confirmation, Disconfirmation, and Informa-tion in Hypothesis Testing , 1987 .

[32]  John D. Bransford,et al.  New approaches to instruction: because wisdom can't be told , 1989 .

[33]  A. Tversky,et al.  Who accepts Savage's axiom? , 1974 .

[34]  B. Fischhoff,et al.  On the Psychology of Experimental Surprises. , 1977 .

[35]  R. Skov,et al.  Information-gathering processes: Diagnosticity, hypothesis-confirmatory strategies, and perceived hypothesis confirmation. , 1986 .

[36]  Y. Trope,et al.  Confirmatory and diagnosing strategies in social information gathering. , 1982 .

[37]  C. Mckenzie (Non)Complementary updating of belief in two hypotheses , 1999, Memory & cognition.

[38]  Karl Halvor Teigen,et al.  Studies in subjective probability III: The unimportance of alternatives , 1983 .

[39]  A. Pike Latency and relative frequency of response in psychophysical discrimination. , 1968, The British journal of mathematical and statistical psychology.

[40]  Janet A. Sniezek,et al.  The effect of choosing on confidence in choice , 1990 .

[41]  Glenn Shafer,et al.  A Mathematical Theory of Evidence , 2020, A Mathematical Theory of Evidence.

[42]  M. Lepper,et al.  Considering the opposite: a corrective strategy for social judgment. , 1984, Journal of personality and social psychology.

[43]  Joshua Klayman,et al.  Debias the environment instead of the judge: an alternative approach to reducing error in diagnostic (and other) judgment , 1993, Cognition.

[44]  J. Klayman Cue discovery in probabilistic environments: Uncertainty and experimentation. , 1988 .

[45]  Rami Zwick,et al.  Comparing the calibration and coherence of numerical and verbal probability judgments , 1993 .