Abductive inference and delusional belief

Delusional beliefs have sometimes been considered as rational inferences from abnormal experiences. We explore this idea in more detail, making the following points. First, the abnormalities of cognition that initially prompt the entertaining of a delusional belief are not always conscious and since we prefer to restrict the term “experience” to consciousness we refer to “abnormal data” rather than “abnormal experience”. Second, we argue that in relation to many delusions (we consider seven) one can clearly identify what the abnormal cognitive data are which prompted the delusion and what the neuropsychological impairment is which is responsible for the occurrence of these data; but one can equally clearly point to cases where this impairment is present but delusion is not. So the impairment is not sufficient for delusion to occur: a second cognitive impairment, one that affects the ability to evaluate beliefs, must also be present. Third (and this is the main thrust of our paper), we consider in detail what the nature of the inference is that leads from the abnormal data to the belief. This is not deductive inference and it is not inference by enumerative induction; it is abductive inference. We offer a Bayesian account of abductive inference and apply it to the explanation of delusional belief.

[1]  W. James,et al.  The Principles of Psychology. , 1983 .

[2]  P. Cz. Handbuch der physiologischen Optik , 1896 .

[3]  Jaakko Hintikka,et al.  On the Logic of Perception , 1969 .

[4]  B. Maher,et al.  Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder. , 1974, Journal of individual psychology.

[5]  Alan S. Brown,et al.  Information Processing and Cognition: The Loyola Symposium , 1976 .

[6]  J. Fodor The Modularity of mind. An essay on faculty psychology , 1986 .

[7]  Z. Pylyshyn Robot's Dilemma: The Frame Problem in Artificial Intelligence , 1987 .

[8]  Judea Pearl,et al.  Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems - networks of plausible inference , 1991, Morgan Kaufmann series in representation and reasoning.

[9]  E. Bisiach,et al.  Remission of somatoparaphrenic delusion through vestibular stimulation , 1991, Neuropsychologia.

[10]  B. Jack Copeland,et al.  Artificial Intelligence: A Philosophical Introduction , 1993 .

[11]  Hanna Damasio,et al.  Double Dissociation between Overt and Covert Face Recognition , 1995, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

[12]  P. Thagard,et al.  Abductive Reasoning: Logic, Visual Thinking, and Coherence , 1997 .

[13]  V. Ramachandran,et al.  Capgras syndrome: a novel probe for understanding the neural representation of the identity and familiarity of persons , 1997, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences.

[14]  Hadyn D. Ellis,et al.  Reduced autonomic responses to faces in Capgras delusion , 1997, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences.

[15]  A. Berthoz,et al.  Functional MRI of galvanic vestibular stimulation. , 1998, Journal of neurophysiology.

[16]  R. J. Seitz,et al.  Mirror agnosia and mirror ataxia constitute different parietal lobe disorders , 1999, Annals of neurology.

[17]  Max Coltheart,et al.  The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions , 2000 .

[18]  Michael B. Lewis,et al.  Automatic without autonomic responses to familiar faces: Differential components of covert face recognition in a case of Capgras delusion , 2000 .

[19]  Rüdiger Wenzel,et al.  Human Vestibular Cortex as Identified with Caloric Stimulation in Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging , 2002, NeuroImage.

[20]  R. Mausfeld,et al.  Perception and the Physical World: Psychological and Philosophical Issues in Perception , 2002 .

[21]  Marc Jeannerod,et al.  Lack of conscious recognition of one's own actions in a haptically deafferented patient , 2002, Neuroreport.

[22]  Pablo Rychter Modularidad y teoría computacional de la mente en la obra de Jerry Fodor: Nota crítica en torno a The Mind Doesn't Work that Way , 2002 .

[23]  N. Valenza,et al.  Hyperfamiliarity for unknown faces after left lateral temporo-occipital venous infarction: a double dissociation with prosopagnosia. , 2003, Brain : a journal of neurology.

[24]  H. D. Critchley,et al.  Social and motivational functioning is not critically dependent on feedback of autonomic responses: neuropsychological evidence from patients with pure autonomic failure , 2004, Neuropsychologia.

[25]  V. P. Misra,et al.  The sympathetic skin response in peripheral autonomic failure — evaluation in pure autonomic failure, pure cholinergic dysautonomia and dopamine-beta-hydroxylase deficiency , 2005, Clinical Autonomic Research.

[26]  P. Schyns,et al.  A mechanism for impaired fear recognition after amygdala damage , 2005, Nature.

[27]  G. Hatfield Perception as Unconscious Inference , 2005 .

[28]  Paul Thagard,et al.  Abductive Inference: From Philosophical Analysis to Neural Mechanisms , 2005 .

[29]  Max Coltheart,et al.  Schizophrenia and monothematic delusions. , 2007, Schizophrenia bulletin.

[30]  M. Coltheart The 33rd Sir Frederick Bartlett Lecture Cognitive neuropsychiatry and delusional belief , 2007 .

[31]  W. N. Schoenfeld,et al.  Principles of Psychology , 2007 .

[32]  G. Brighetti,et al.  “Far from the heart far from the eye”: Evidence from the Capgras delusion , 2007, Cognitive neuropsychiatry.

[33]  Max Coltheart,et al.  Confabulation and delusion , 2009 .

[34]  M. Coltheart,et al.  Confabulation and delusion: A common monitoring framework , 2010, Cognitive neuropsychiatry.

[35]  D. McDermott LANGUAGE OF THOUGHT , 2012 .