Are There Necessary Conditions for Inducing a Sense of Sarcastic Irony?

This article investigates the contextual components utilized to convey sarcastic verbal irony, testing whether theoretical components deemed as necessary for creating a sense of irony are, in fact, necessary. A novel task was employed: Given a set of statements that out of context were not rated as sarcastic, participants were instructed to either generate discourse context that would make the statements sarcastic or meaningful (without further specification). In a series of studies, these generated contexts were shown to differ from one another along the dimensions presumed as necessary (failed expectation, pragmatic insincerity, negative tension, and presence of a victim) and along stylistic components (as indexed by the Linguistic Inquiry and Word Count program). However, none of these components were found to be necessary. Indeed, in each case, the items rated as highest in sarcasm were often at the lowest levels on the putative “necessary” characteristic. These data are taken as consistent with constraint satisfaction models of sarcasm processing in which various linguistic and extralinguistic information provide probabilistic (but not necessary) support for or against a sarcastic interpretation.

[1]  J. Searle Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts , 1979 .

[2]  Philip A. Higham,et al.  Recourse to Stored Exemplars is not Necessarily Explicit: A Comment on Knowlton, Ramus, and Squire (1992) , 1994 .

[3]  R. Kreuz,et al.  Why Do People Use Figurative Language? , 1994 .

[4]  S. Glucksberg,et al.  How about another piece of pie: the allusional pretense theory of discourse irony. , 1995, Journal of experimental psychology. General.

[5]  Julie C. Sedivy,et al.  Resolving attachment ambiguities with multiple constraints , 1995, Cognition.

[6]  James A. Hampton,et al.  Testing the Prototype Theory of Concepts , 1995 .

[7]  Penny M. Pexman,et al.  Interpreting Figurative Statements: Speaker Occupation Can Change Metaphor to Irony , 1997 .

[8]  Albert N. Katz,et al.  The Differential Role of Ridicule in Sarcasm and Irony , 1998 .

[9]  Todd R. Ferretti,et al.  Discourse Factors That Influence Online Reading of Metaphor and Irony , 2000 .

[10]  P. Rockwell,et al.  Lower, Slower, Louder: Vocal Cues of Sarcasm , 2000 .

[11]  A. Utsumi Verbal irony as implicit display of ironic environment: Distinguishing ironic utterances from nonirony☆ , 2000 .

[12]  Herbert L. Colston,et al.  On necessary conditions for verbal irony comprehension , 2000 .

[13]  A. Katz,et al.  On the uses of sarcastic irony , 2000 .

[14]  Todd R. Ferretti,et al.  Moment-By-Moment Reading of Proverbs in Literal and Nonliteral Contexts , 2001 .

[15]  R. Giora On Our Mind: Salience, Context, and Figurative Language , 2003 .

[16]  J. Pennebaker,et al.  Lying Words: Predicting Deception from Linguistic Styles , 2003, Personality & social psychology bulletin.

[17]  P. Pexman It's Fascinating Research , 2008 .

[18]  Carla J. Groom,et al.  Gender Differences in Language Use: An Analysis of 14,000 Text Samples , 2008 .

[19]  Geert Brône,et al.  Does an “ironic situation” favor an ironic interpretation? , 2009 .

[20]  Csr Young,et al.  How to Do Things With Words , 2009 .

[21]  Albert Katz,et al.  When Sarcasm Stings , 2011 .