The effect of "irrelevant" variables on decision making: Criterion shifts in preferential choice?

Abstract In decision research, it is widely assumed that decision makers have subjective experiences which indicate definitively, albeit with random fluctuations, whether or not one alternative is preferable to another. Further, it is assumed that subjects' choices reflect this underlying preference order. It follows from this position, as a logical consequence rather than an empirical observation, that if a manipulation affects people's choices, it does so by changing the way people subjectively experience the alternatives (presumably via people's encoding or combination of attribute information). In psychophysics, an analogous theoretical position has been relinquished. Specifically, it is no longer believed that observers in a detection experiment have subjective experiences which indicate definitively, albeit with error, whether a signal has been perceived. Rather, according to signal detection theory, the observer's sensory experience can be portrayed as a quantifiable sensation that must be converted into an overt report of “signal present” or “signal absent” by comparing the sensation with a criterion. In this paper, we describe two models of preferential choice, the lexicographic criterion model and a probabilistic criterion model, that replace the notion of definitive preference with an analogue of signal detection theory. In the models, the decision maker is represented as having quantifiable inclinations, rather than definitive preferences, that must be converted into an overt choice by comparing the inclinations with a criterion. By attributing the effects of experimental manipulations to shifts in the criterion, rather than to changes in people's inclinations, the model offers a testable alternative to the proposition that altered choices imply altered preferences.

[1]  R. Luce Semiorders and a Theory of Utility Discrimination , 1956 .

[2]  L. Guttman A basis for scaling qualitative data. , 1944 .

[3]  Louis Narens,et al.  Measurement: The theory of numerical assignments. , 1986 .

[4]  Baruch Fischhoff,et al.  Response Mode, Framing and Information-processing Effects in Risk Assessment , 1988 .

[5]  L. A. Goodman Simple statistical methods for scalogram analysis , 1959 .

[6]  William Samuelson,et al.  Status quo bias in decision making , 1988 .

[7]  Colleen F. Surber,et al.  Issues in Using Quantitative Rating Scales in Developmental Research , 1984 .

[8]  A. Tversky,et al.  The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. , 1981, Science.

[9]  J. Baron,et al.  Investigating the effect of stimulus range on attribute weight. , 1991, Journal of experimental psychology. Human perception and performance.

[10]  C. Coombs,et al.  On the use of inconsistency of preferences in psychological measurement. , 1958, Journal of experimental psychology.

[11]  Jean-Claude Falmagne,et al.  A Probabilistic Theory of Extensive Measurement , 1980, Philosophy of Science.

[12]  G. Pitz,et al.  Judgment and decision: theory and application. , 1984, Annual review of psychology.

[13]  P. C. Sagi A statistical test for the significance of a coefficient of reproducibility , 1959 .

[14]  A. Tversky,et al.  Foundations of Measurement, Vol. III: Representation, Axiomatization, and Invariance , 1990 .

[15]  Robert Sugden,et al.  Probability and juxtaposition effects: An experimental investigation of the common ratio effect , 1989 .

[16]  Jerome R. Busemeyer,et al.  Linking together different measures of preference: A dynamic model of matching derived from decision field theory , 1992 .

[17]  Jean-Claude Falmagne,et al.  A representation theorem for finite random scale systems , 1978 .

[18]  P. Slovic,et al.  Reversals of preference between bids and choices in gambling decisions. , 1971 .

[19]  Jean-Claude Falmagne,et al.  Statistical issues in measurement , 1985 .

[20]  A. Tversky,et al.  Substitutability and similarity in binary choices , 1969 .

[21]  Paul Slovic,et al.  Response-induced reversals of preference in gambling: An extended replication in las vegas , 1973 .

[22]  A. Tversky,et al.  Contingent weighting in judgment and choice , 1988 .

[23]  Howard Wainer,et al.  The Rasch Model as Additive Conjoint Measurement , 1979 .

[24]  Patrick Suppes,et al.  Foundational aspects of theories of measurement , 1958, Journal of Symbolic Logic.

[25]  Michael H. Birnbaum,et al.  A change-of-process theory for contextual effects and preference reversals in risky decision making , 1992 .

[26]  John W. Payne,et al.  Contingent decision behavior. , 1982 .

[27]  Preference and the time to choose , 1977 .

[28]  G. Iverson,et al.  Binaural "loudness" summation: probabilistic theory and data. , 1979, Psychological review.

[29]  P. Vincke,et al.  Biorder families, valued relations and preference modelling , 1986 .

[30]  Christopher P. Puto,et al.  Adding Asymmetrically Dominated Alternatives: Violations of Regularity & the Similarity Hypothesis. , 1981 .

[31]  A. Tversky Intransitivity of preferences. , 1969 .

[32]  P. Fishburn Intransitive indifference with unequal indifference intervals , 1970 .

[33]  William M. Goldstein,et al.  The relative importance of relative importance: Inferring other people's preferences from relative importance ratings and previous decisions , 1992 .

[34]  Peter C. Fishburn,et al.  Intransitive Indifference in Preference Theory: A Survey , 1970, Oper. Res..

[35]  Roman Krzysztofowicz,et al.  Strength of preference and risk attitude in utility measurement , 1983 .

[36]  D. Jamieson,et al.  Studying preferential choice without stable probability estimates: temporal transitivity analyses , 1976 .

[37]  H. J. Einhorn,et al.  Expression theory and the preference reversal phenomena. , 1987 .

[38]  J. Falmagne Random Conjoint Measurement and Loudness Summation. , 1976 .

[39]  Eric J. Johnson,et al.  Adaptive Strategy Selection in Decision Making. , 1988 .

[40]  J. Falmagne On a class of probabilistic conjoint measurement models: Some diagnostic properties☆ , 1979 .

[41]  J. Busemeyer Decision making under uncertainty: a comparison of simple scalability, fixed-sample, and sequential-sampling models. , 1985, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[42]  Jean-Claude Falmagne,et al.  Conjoint Weber laws and additivity , 1979 .

[43]  L. Thurstone A law of comparative judgment. , 1994 .

[44]  R. Hogarth,et al.  BEHAVIORAL DECISION THEORY: PROCESSES OF JUDGMENT AND CHOICE , 1981 .

[45]  Rakesh K. Sarin,et al.  Measurable Multiattribute Value Functions , 1979, Oper. Res..

[46]  Rakesh K. Sarin,et al.  RELATIVE RISK AVERSION. , 1982 .

[47]  Bert F. Green,et al.  A method of scalogram analysis using summary statistics , 1956 .

[48]  Colin Camerer An experimental test of several generalized utility theories , 1989 .

[49]  Patrick Suppes,et al.  Foundations of Measurement, Vol. II: Geometrical, Threshold, and Probabilistic Representations , 1989 .

[50]  Frederick Mosteller,et al.  An Experimental Measurement of Utility , 1951, Journal of Political Economy.

[51]  Michael H. Birnbaum,et al.  Loci of contextual effects in judgment. , 1982 .

[52]  Michael H. Birnbaum,et al.  Contextual effects in social judgment , 1983 .

[53]  Eric J. Johnson,et al.  The Adaptive Decision-Maker : Effort and Accuracy in Choice , 2022 .

[54]  Jean-Paul Doignon,et al.  On realizable biorders and the biorder dimension of a relation , 1984 .