Epistemological Strata and the Rules of Right Reason

It has been commonplace in epistemology since its inception to idealize away from computational resource constraints, i.e., from the constraints of time and memory. One thought is that a kind of ideal rationality can be specified that ignores the constraints imposed by limited time and memory, and that actual cognitive performance can be seen as an interaction between the norms of ideal rationality and the practicalities of time and memory limitations. But a cornerstone of naturalistic epistemology is that normative assessment is constrained by capacities: you cannot require someone to do something they cannot or, as it is usually put, ought implies can. This much we take to be uncontroversial. We argue that differences in architectures, goals and resources imply substantial differences in capacity, and that some of these differences are ineliminable. It follows that some differences in goals and architectural and computational resources matter at the normative level: they constrain what principles of normative epistemology can be used to describe and prescribe their behavior. As a result, we can expect there to be important epistemic differences between the way brains, individuals, and science work.

[1]  L. Cosmides,et al.  The Adapted mind : evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture , 1992 .

[2]  Dana H. Ballard,et al.  Animate Vision , 1991, Artif. Intell..

[3]  P. Churchland Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind , 1980 .

[4]  Arnold B. Scheibel,et al.  The Origin and Evolution of Intelligence , 1997 .

[5]  N A Fox,et al.  Definitions and concepts of emotion regulation. Introduction. , 1994, Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development.

[6]  Zenon W. Pylyshyn,et al.  Connectionism and cognitive architecture , 1993 .

[7]  I. Hacking,et al.  How Experiments End , 1989 .

[8]  Allen Newell,et al.  Elements of a theory of human problem solving. , 1958 .

[9]  H. Eichenbaum,et al.  Memory, amnesia, and the hippocampal system , 1993 .

[10]  John Haugeland,et al.  Artificial intelligence - the very idea , 1987 .

[11]  T. Kuhn,et al.  The Structure of Scientific Revolutions , 1963 .

[12]  N. Chater,et al.  Computational models and Rethinking innateness , 1999, Journal of Child Language.

[13]  Edwin Hutchins,et al.  How a Cockpit Remembers Its Speeds , 1995, Cogn. Sci..

[14]  A. Noë,et al.  A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. , 2001, The Behavioral and brain sciences.

[15]  A. Gopnik,et al.  Words, thoughts, and theories , 1997 .

[16]  P. Teller Twilight Of The Perfect Model Model , 2001 .

[17]  M. Merleau-Ponty Phénoménologie de la perception , 1950 .

[18]  A. Goldman Knowledge in a Social World , 1999 .

[19]  John Preston,et al.  The Engine of Reason, The Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain , 1996 .

[20]  Elissa L. Newport,et al.  Maturational Constraints on Language Learning , 1990, Cogn. Sci..

[21]  D. Cummins,et al.  Biological preparedness and evolutionary explanation , 1999, Cognition.

[22]  Andy Clark,et al.  Moving Minds: Situating Content in the Service of Real-Time Success , 1995 .

[23]  Martin D. Ringle Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology , 1982 .

[24]  J. Fodor,et al.  Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis , 1988, Cognition.

[25]  P. Churchland Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes , 1993 .

[26]  T. Sejnowski,et al.  A critique of pure vision , 1993 .

[27]  J. Elman Learning and development in neural networks: the importance of starting small , 1993, Cognition.

[28]  Robert Cummins,et al.  Connectionism and the Rationale Constraint on Cognitive Explanation , 1995 .

[29]  A. Flew,et al.  Patterns of Discovery. , 1961 .

[30]  John McCarthy,et al.  What Computers Still Can't Do , 1996, Artif. Intell..

[31]  R. Cummins The nature of psychological explanation , 1983 .

[32]  Robert M. French,et al.  Catastrophic Interference in Connectionist Networks: Can It Be Predicted, Can It Be Prevented? , 1993, NIPS.

[33]  R. Cummins Representations, targets, and attitudes , 1996 .

[34]  L. Cosmides,et al.  THEPODULAR NATURE OF HUMAN INTELLIGENCE , 1997 .

[35]  P. Churchland A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science , 1989 .

[36]  S. Pinker How the Mind Works , 1999, Philosophy after Darwin.

[37]  R. Samuels Evolutionary Psychology and the Massive Modularity Hypothesis , 1998, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

[38]  A. Tversky,et al.  On the psychology of prediction , 1973 .

[39]  L. Cosmides,et al.  The psychological foundations of culture. , 1992 .

[40]  Pierre Poirier,et al.  Systematicity and the Cognition of Structured Domains , 2001 .

[41]  J. Fodor The Appeal to Tacit Knowledge in Psychological Explanation , 1968 .

[42]  John Tooby,et al.  From evolution to behavior: Evolutionary psychology as the missing link. , 1987 .

[43]  G. A. Miller,et al.  Book Review Nisbett, R. , & Ross, L.Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgment.Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1980. , 1982 .

[44]  John L. Pollock,et al.  How to Build a Person: A Prolegomenon , 1992, IEEE Expert.

[45]  J. Fodor The Modularity of mind. An essay on faculty psychology , 1986 .

[46]  Edwin Hutchins How a Cockpit Remembers Its Speeds , 1995 .

[47]  S. Gelman,et al.  Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity In Cognition And Culture , 1994 .

[48]  D. Rumelhart,et al.  Philosophy and Connectionist Theory , 1991 .

[49]  I. Nonaka,et al.  The Knowledge Creating Company , 2008 .

[50]  Ruth Garrett Millikan,et al.  Pushmi-Pullyu Representations , 1995 .

[51]  R. Giere Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach , 1991 .

[52]  Michael McCloskey,et al.  Catastrophic Interference in Connectionist Networks: The Sequential Learning Problem , 1989 .

[53]  James L. McClelland,et al.  Why there are complementary learning systems in the hippocampus and neocortex: insights from the successes and failures of connectionist models of learning and memory. , 1995, Psychological review.

[54]  Michael A. Arbib,et al.  Perceptual Structures and Distributed Motor Control , 1981 .

[55]  A. Galaburda,et al.  Evidence for a Magnocellular Defect in Developmental Dyslexia a , 1993, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences.

[56]  A. Clark,et al.  Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. , 1988 .

[57]  H. Putnam,et al.  The analytic and the synthetic , 1962 .

[58]  J. Fodor The Mind Doesn't Work That Way : The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology , 2000 .

[59]  L. Cosmides,et al.  Mapping the mind: Origins of domain specificity: The evolution of functional organization , 1994 .

[60]  F. N. Dempster,et al.  Memory Span: Sources of Individual and Developmental Differences , 1981 .

[61]  H. Feigl,et al.  Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science , 1956 .

[62]  R. Cummins Meaning and mental representation , 1990 .

[63]  Lynn Waterhouse,et al.  Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain , 1988 .

[64]  M. Snowling Foundations of reading acquisition and dyslexia: Implications for early intervention. , 2000 .

[65]  David Hume A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to introduce the experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects , 1972 .

[66]  James L. McClelland,et al.  Explorations in parallel distributed processing: a handbook of models, programs, and exercises , 1988 .

[67]  L. Cosmides,et al.  Mapping the mind: Origins of domain specificity: The evolution of functional organization , 1994 .

[68]  W. Wimsatt Forms of Aggregativity , 1986 .