Intentional Gaps In Mathematical Proofs

A central question in the philosophy of mathematics is: How do mathematicians know that mathematical propositions are true? The standard answer is that a mathematician knows that a proposition is true because she knows a proof of that proposition. Of course, this answer leaves a couple of important things unexplained. First, how does the mathematician know that the axioms that her proof appeals to (e.g., the axiom of choice) are true? Second, how does the mathematician know that the rules of inference that her proof appeals to (e.g., the law of the excluded middle) are truth preserving? A lot of work in the philosophy of mathematics has gone into trying to give answers to these two questions (see, e.g., Maddy 1988). In this paper, I argue that even if we had completely satisfactory answers to these two questions, we would still not have a completely satisfactory explanation of how mathematicians actually know on the basis of proof that mathematical propositions are true. The reason is that mathematicians often intentionally leave gaps in their proofs.

[1]  Peter J. Denning,et al.  The science of computing , 1989 .

[2]  Imre Lakatos,et al.  On the Uses of Rigorous Proof. (Book Reviews: Proofs and Refutations. The Logic of Mathematical Discovery) , 1977 .

[3]  Leonid A. Levin,et al.  Checking computations in polylogarithmic time , 1991, STOC '91.

[4]  Kurt Gödel,et al.  On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems , 1966 .

[5]  Henri Poincaré Science and Method , 1914 .

[6]  P. Wallis,et al.  A Source Book in Mathematics, 1200-1800 , 1971, The Mathematical Gazette.

[7]  P. Kitcher,et al.  An opinionated introduction , 1988 .

[8]  Joseph R. Shoenfield,et al.  Mathematical logic , 1967 .

[9]  W. S. Anglin MATHEMATICS AND VALUE , 1991 .

[10]  R. Hersh Proving is convincing and explaining , 1993 .

[11]  Penelope Maddy,et al.  Believing the axioms. I , 1988, Journal of Symbolic Logic.

[12]  D. Fallis The Epistemic Status of Probabilistic Proof , 1997 .

[13]  Ian Stewart,et al.  From Here to Infinity , 1996 .

[14]  M. Rabin Probabilistic algorithm for testing primality , 1980 .

[15]  R. Kershner,et al.  On Paving the Plane , 1968 .

[16]  Mario Bunge,et al.  The methodological unity of science , 1973 .

[17]  John Corcoran Gaps between Logical Theory and Mathematical Practice , 1973 .

[18]  W. W. Ball,et al.  A Short Account of the History of Mathematics . By Walter W. R. Ball. London and New York, Macmillan. 12°. $2.60 , 1888, Science.

[19]  Robert H. Anderson,et al.  A Source Book , 1995 .

[20]  S. Smale The fundamental theorem of algebra and complexity theory , 1981 .

[21]  T. L. H.,et al.  The Geometry of René Descartes , 1926, Nature.

[22]  Jody Azzouni,et al.  Metaphysical Myths, Mathematical Practice: Acknowledgments , 1994 .

[23]  Gottlob Frege,et al.  The Foundations of Arithmetic , 2017 .

[24]  Jean Dieudonne The Concept of 'Rigorous Proof' , 1996 .

[25]  J. Dawson,et al.  The Reception of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems , 1984, PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

[26]  Saunders Mac Lane,et al.  Structure in Mathematics , 1996, The Metaphysics and Mathematics of Arbitrary Objects.

[27]  Herbert B. Enderton,et al.  A mathematical introduction to logic , 1972 .

[28]  Doris Schattschneider,et al.  In Praise of Amateurs , 1981 .

[29]  Philip Kitcher,et al.  The nature of mathematical knowledge , 1985 .

[30]  G. Pólya Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning , 1958 .

[31]  Philip J. Davis,et al.  Fidelity in mathematical discourse: is one and one really two? , 1972 .

[32]  J. Hadamard,et al.  The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field. , 1945 .