Perception as Unconscious Inference

Consider for a moment the spatial and chromatic dimensions of your visual experience. Suppose that as you gaze about the room you see a table, some books, and papers. Ignore for now the fact that you immediately recognize these objects to be a table with books and papers on it. Concentrate on how the table looks to you: its top spreads out in front of you, stopping at edges beyond which lies unfilled space, leading to more or less distant chairs, shelves, or expanses of floor. The books and paper on the table top create shaped visual boundaries between areas of different color, within which there may be further variation of color or visual texture. Propelled by a slight breeze, a sheet of paper slides across the table, and you experience its smooth motion before it floats out of sight. The aspects of visual perception to which I’ve drawn your attention are objects of study in contemporary perceptual psychology, which considers the perception of size, shape, distance, motion, and color. These phenomenal aspects of vision are sometimes contrasted with other, more typically cognitive aspects of perception, including our recognition that the objects in front of us include the table, books, and paper, our seeing that the table is old and well crafted, and our identifying the sheets of paper as the draft of an article in progress. All of these elements of our visual experience, whether characterized here as phenomenal or cognitive,1 seem to arise effortlessly as we direct our gaze here and there. Yet we know that the cognitive aspects must depend on previously attained knowledge. We are not born recognizing books and tables, but we learn to categorize these artifacts and to determine at a glance that a table is an old one of good quality. What about the phenomenal aspects? A persistent theme in the history of visual theory has been that the phenomenal aspects of visual perception are produced by inferences or judgments, which are

[1]  Ewald Hering,et al.  Grundzüge der Lehre vom Lichtsinn. , 1920 .

[2]  K. Koffka Principles Of Gestalt Psychology , 1936 .

[3]  C. E. SHANNON,et al.  A mathematical theory of communication , 1948, MOCO.

[4]  F. Attneave Some informational aspects of visual perception. , 1954, Psychological review.

[5]  E. Brunswik Perception and the Representative Design of Psychological Experiments , 1957 .

[6]  Molière,et al.  le malade imaginaire , 1965 .

[7]  R. Gregory Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing , 1966 .

[8]  J. Gibson The Senses Considered As Perceptual Systems , 1967 .

[9]  J. Gibson The legacies of Koffka's Principles. , 1971, Journal of the history of the behavioral sciences.

[10]  H. Helmholtz,et al.  Selected writings of Hermann von Helmholtz , 1971 .

[11]  René Descartes,et al.  The Treatise on Man , 1972 .

[12]  H. Barlow Inductive Inference, Coding, Perception, and Language , 1974, Perception.

[13]  L. Kaufman Sight and mind : an introduction to visual perception , 1974 .

[14]  S. Runeson On the possibility of "smart" perceptual mechanisms. , 1977, Scandinavian journal of psychology.

[15]  G. Kanizsa,et al.  Organization in Vision: Essays on Gestalt Perception , 1979 .

[16]  W. Epstein,et al.  The Sensory Core and the Medieval Foundations of Early Modern Perceptual Theory , 1979, Isis.

[17]  S. Howard Bartley,et al.  Introduction to Perception , 1980 .

[18]  R. Gregory Perceptions as hypotheses. , 1980, Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological sciences.

[19]  William P. Alston,et al.  Knowledge and the Flow of Information , 1985 .

[20]  David Marr,et al.  VISION A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information , 2009 .

[21]  Stephen M. Kosslyn,et al.  Ghosts in the mind's machine: Creating and using images in the brain , 1983 .

[22]  S. Kosslyn,et al.  Representation without symbol systems , 1984 .

[23]  Zenon W. Pylyshyn,et al.  Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science , 1984 .

[24]  J. Fodor,et al.  The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology , 1984 .

[25]  G. Kanizsa Seeing and thinking. , 1985, Acta psychologica.

[26]  L. Maloney,et al.  Color constancy: a method for recovering surface spectral reflectance. , 1986, Journal of the Optical Society of America. A, Optics and image science.

[27]  James E. Cutting,et al.  Perception with an eye for motion , 1986 .

[28]  G. Hatfield Representation and content in some (actual) theories of perception , 1988 .

[29]  Ephraim ca. Chambers,et al.  Cyclopædia, or, An universal dictionary of arts and sciences , 1988 .

[30]  Dominic W. Massaro,et al.  Observer Mechanics: A Formal Theory of Perception , 1989 .

[31]  Fred I. Dretske Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes , 1990 .

[32]  M. Atherton Berkeley's Revolution in Vision , 2019 .

[33]  H. Barlow Conditions for versatile learning, Helmholtz's unconscious inference, and the task of perception , 1990, Vision Research.

[34]  Michael A. Arbib,et al.  Vision, brain, and cooperative computation: an overview , 1990 .

[35]  T. Goldsmith Optimization, Constraint, and History in the Evolution of Eyes , 1990, The Quarterly Review of Biology.

[36]  Gary Hatfield,et al.  Representation and Rule-Instantiation in Connectionist Systems , 1991 .

[37]  Kim Sterelny,et al.  The Imagery Debate , 1991 .

[38]  Gary Hatfield The Natural and the Normative: Theories of Spatial Perception from Kant to Helmholtz , 1991 .

[39]  A. Rosenfeld Vision: Pyramid algorithms for efficient vision , 1991 .

[40]  T. Natsoulas “Why do things look as they do?” Some Gibsonian answers to Koffka's question , 1991 .

[41]  K. Hutchison Dormitive Virtues, Scholastic Qualities, and the New Philosophies , 1991 .

[42]  Philip T. Quinlan,et al.  Connectionsim and psychology - a psychological perspective on new connectionist research , 1991 .

[43]  Tim Crane,et al.  The Nonconceptual Content of Experience , 1992 .

[44]  G. Hatfield Color Perception and Neural Encoding: Does Metameric Matching Entail a Loss of Information? , 1992, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

[45]  G. Hatfield,et al.  Descartes' physiology and its relation to his psychology , 1992 .

[46]  Vision: Variations on Some Berkeleian Themes , 1993 .

[47]  Thomas D. Albright,et al.  Why do things look as they do? , 1994, Trends in Neurosciences.

[48]  S. Kosslyn Image and Brain: The Resolution of the Imagery Debate , 1994, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

[49]  B. Wandell Foundations of vision , 1995 .

[50]  M. Tye Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind , 1997 .

[51]  Shinsuke Shimojo,et al.  Visual surface representation: a critical link between lower-level and higher level vision , 1995 .

[52]  Kirk Ludwig Explaining why things look the way they do , 1996 .

[53]  D. Cahan,et al.  Science and Culture: Popular and Philosophical Essays by Hermann von Helmholtz , 1996 .

[54]  E S E a R C H , 1997 .

[55]  Vincent Walsh,et al.  Perceptual Constancy: why things look as they do , 1998 .

[56]  K. Clark CONDITIONS FOR VERSATILE LEARNING , HELMHOLTZ ’ S UNCONSCIOUS INFERENCE , AND THE TASK OF PERCEPTION , 2002 .

[57]  Robert L. Goldstone,et al.  Concepts and Categorization , 2003 .

[58]  G. Berkeley Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision , 2004 .

[59]  Georges Rey,et al.  Language of Thought , 2006 .