Associative anaphora and its interpretation

Abstract When readers or hearers interpret a definite associative NP, they must take into account that all definite NPs carry a presupposition of existential uniqueness. This implies that hearers or readers can access an entity which is presented as the only one of the type expressed by the N of the definite NP. In the case of associative definites which introduce a new entity, this entity must be easily accessible through, for instance, a definite NP1. Stereotypical part-whole relations are a case in point where such accessibility exists between the entities designated by NP1 and NP2. The fact that a definite associative NP2 must be supported by an accessibility relation explains why the use of a definite associative NP2 comes across as strange, should a part-whole relation be transitive. Problems also arise when the hearer or reader has no previous knowledge about the links between the entities denoted by the definite NP2 and the preceding NP1. In this case the context may offer several candidates for the role of antecedent and favor a coreferential or associative interpretation. The last part of the paper is devoted to a discussion of examples of this type of context and argues in favour of an approach to associative anaphora that takes into account diverse, and possibly contradictory, contextual clues in the utterance where NP1 is employed.

[1]  M. Walker,et al.  Centering Theory in Discourse , 1998 .

[2]  Eleanor Rosch,et al.  Principles of Categorization , 1978 .

[3]  W. Heydrich,et al.  Connexity and Coherence: Analysis of Text and Discourse , 1989 .

[4]  Jeanette K. Gundel Relevance theory meets the givenness hierarchy: an account of inferrables , 1996 .

[5]  J. Hawkins On (in)definite articles: implicatures and (un)grammaticality prediction , 1991, Journal of Linguistics.

[6]  B. Fradin,et al.  Anaphorisation et stereotypes nominaux , 1984 .

[7]  Georges Kleiber,et al.  Associative anaphora and part-whole relationship: The condition of alienation and the principle of ontological congruence , 1999 .

[8]  M. Walker,et al.  A bilateral approach to givenness : A hearer-status algorithm and a centering algorithm , 1996 .

[9]  Ellen F. Prince,et al.  Toward a taxonomy of given-new information , 1981 .

[10]  J. Hawkins Definiteness and indefiniteness: a study in reference and grammaticality prediction , 1978 .

[11]  John R. Anderson A spreading activation theory of memory. , 1983 .

[12]  Mira Ariel Accessing Noun-Phrase Antecedents , 1990 .

[13]  G. Kleiber Quand il n'a pas d'antécédent , 1990 .

[14]  S. Garrod,et al.  Understanding written language: Explorations of comprehension beyond the sentence , 1981 .

[15]  John A. Hawkins,et al.  A note on referent identifiability and co-presence , 1984 .

[16]  S. S. Culbert,et al.  Cognition and Categorization , 1979 .

[17]  Donna Jo Napoli,et al.  Agreement and anaphora : a study of the role of pronouns in syntax and discourse , 1985 .

[18]  Michel Charolles,et al.  Coherence as a principle in the interpretation of discourse , 1983 .

[19]  Jeanette K. Gundel,et al.  Cognitive Status and the form of Referring Expressions in Discourse , 1993, The Oxford Handbook of Reference.

[20]  Scott Weinstein,et al.  Centering: A Framework for Modeling the Local Coherence of Discourse , 1995, CL.

[21]  F. Cornish Anaphoric Relations in English and French: A Discourse Perspective , 1986 .

[22]  G. Kleiber Anaphore associative, thése lexico-stéréotypique: oui, mais , 1995 .

[23]  Kari Fraurud,et al.  Definiteness and the Processing of Noun Phrases in Natural Discourse , 1990, J. Semant..

[24]  Bonnie L. Webber,et al.  Tense as Discourse Anaphor , 1988, CL.

[25]  Michel Charolles,et al.  Cohésion, cohérence et pertinence du discours , 1995 .

[26]  A comment on John Hawkins' ‘A note on referent identifiability and co-presence’ , 1987 .