Over-representation of Extreme Events in Decision-Making: A Rational Metacognitive Account

The Availability bias, manifested in the over-representation of extreme eventualities in decision-making, is a well-known cognitive bias, and is generally taken as evidence of human irrationality. In this work, we present the first rational, metacognitive account of the Availability bias, formally articulated at Marr's algorithmic level of analysis. Concretely, we present a normative, metacognitive model of how a cognitive system should over-represent extreme eventualities, depending on the amount of time available at its disposal for decision-making. Our model also accounts for two well-known framing effects in human decision-making under risk---the fourfold pattern of risk preferences in outcome probability (Tversky & Kahneman, 1992) and in outcome magnitude (Markovitz, 1952)---thereby providing the first metacognitively-rational basis for those effects. Empirical evidence, furthermore, confirms an important prediction of our model. Surprisingly, our model is unimaginably robust with respect to its focal parameter. We discuss the implications of our work for studies on human decision-making, and conclude by presenting a counterintuitive prediction of our model, which, if confirmed, would have intriguing implications for human decision-making under risk. To our knowledge, our model is the first metacognitive, resource-rational process model of cognitive biases in decision-making.

[1]  Thomas L. Griffiths,et al.  Neural Implementation of Hierarchical Bayesian Inference by Importance Sampling , 2009, NIPS.

[2]  P. Berkes,et al.  Statistically Optimal Perception and Learning: from Behavior to Neural Representations , 2022 .

[3]  A. Tversky,et al.  Subjective Probability: A Judgment of Representativeness , 1972 .

[4]  Ola Svenson,et al.  Time pressure and stress in human judgment and decision making , 1993 .

[5]  J. Geweke,et al.  Bayesian Inference in Econometric Models Using Monte Carlo Integration , 1989 .

[6]  R. Rescorla,et al.  A theory of Pavlovian conditioning : Variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement , 1972 .

[7]  J. Tenenbaum,et al.  Optimal Predictions in Everyday Cognition , 2006, Psychological science.

[8]  J. Neumann,et al.  The Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour , 1944 .

[9]  Alexander J. Rothman,et al.  Absolute and Relative Biases in Estimations of Personal Risk , 1996 .

[10]  Adam N Sanborn,et al.  Exemplar models as a mechanism for performing Bayesian inference , 2010, Psychonomic bulletin & review.

[11]  R. Hertwig Decisions from Experience , 2015 .

[12]  K. Kontek On Mental Transformations , 2009 .

[13]  Samuel J. Gershman,et al.  Computational rationality: A converging paradigm for intelligence in brains, minds, and machines , 2015, Science.

[14]  R. Zeckhauser,et al.  Overreaction to Fearsome Risks , 2008 .

[15]  Adam N. Sanborn,et al.  Bridging Levels of Analysis for Probabilistic Models of Cognition , 2012 .

[16]  S. Denison,et al.  Rational variability in children’s causal inferences: The Sampling Hypothesis , 2013, Cognition.

[17]  H. Vincent Poor,et al.  An Introduction to Signal Detection and Estimation , 1994, Springer Texts in Electrical Engineering.

[18]  D. Read,et al.  The Psychology of Intertemporal Tradeoffs , 2009, Psychological review.

[19]  H. Markowitz The Utility of Wealth , 1952, Journal of Political Economy.

[20]  Ola Svenson,et al.  Theoretical and Empirical Approaches to Behavioral Decision Making and Their Relation to Time Constraints , 1993 .

[21]  Falk Lieder,et al.  Overrepresentation of Extreme Events in Decision Making Reflects Rational Use of Cognitive Resources , 2017, Psychological review.

[22]  Joshua B. Tenenbaum,et al.  Multistability and Perceptual Inference , 2012, Neural Computation.

[23]  Richard S. Sutton,et al.  Reinforcement Learning: An Introduction , 1998, IEEE Trans. Neural Networks.

[24]  Thomas L. Griffiths,et al.  The high availability of extreme events serves resource-rational decision-making , 2014, CogSci.

[25]  H. Rachlin Diminishing marginal value as delay discounting. , 1992, Journal of the experimental analysis of behavior.

[26]  D. Read,et al.  Prospect theory and the “forgotten” fourfold pattern of risk preferences , 2014 .

[27]  S. Denison,et al.  Probabilistic models, learning algorithms, and response variability: sampling in cognitive development , 2014, Trends in Cognitive Sciences.

[28]  P. Schoemaker,et al.  Prospect theory's reflection hypothesis: A critical examination , 1980 .

[29]  Jessica B. Hamrick,et al.  Simulation as an engine of physical scene understanding , 2013, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

[30]  Kris N Kirby,et al.  An empirical assessment of the form of utility functions. , 2011, Journal of experimental psychology. Learning, memory, and cognition.

[31]  Thomas L. Griffiths,et al.  One and Done? Optimal Decisions From Very Few Samples , 2014, Cogn. Sci..

[32]  J. Neumann,et al.  Theory of games and economic behavior , 1945, 100 Years of Math Milestones.

[33]  J. Hammersley,et al.  Monte Carlo Methods , 1965 .

[34]  S. Cabib,et al.  Positive and negative emotional arousal increases duration of memory traces: common and independent mechanisms , 2011, Front. Behav. Neurosci..

[35]  Timothy J. Pleskac,et al.  Decisions from experience: Why small samples? , 2010, Cognition.

[36]  Joshua B. Tenenbaum,et al.  Building machines that learn and think like people , 2016, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

[37]  T. Başar,et al.  A New Approach to Linear Filtering and Prediction Problems , 2001 .

[38]  A. Tversky,et al.  Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty , 1992 .

[39]  B. Fischhoff,et al.  Judged frequency of lethal events , 1978 .